Author 552
The Homoiomeries of Anaxagoras, 1927
By: Leon, Philip
Title The Homoiomeries of Anaxagoras
Type Article
Language English
Date 1927
Journal The Classical Quarterly
Volume 21
Issue 3/4
Pages 133-141
Categories no categories
Author(s) Leon, Philip
Editor(s)
Translator(s)
[Conclusion, p. 141]: Anaxagoras does indeed, as he has been said to do, represent the culminating point of the enquiry into the one bto-tv. That simple enquiry for a simple unity becomes curiously complex, just because of the very simplicity and the thorough-going and uncompromising nature of Anaxagoras' logical mind. It has with him reached a stage where it must become transformed and pass on the one hand into logic in Plato, into the enquiry about the nature of predication through Gorgias and Antisthenes, and on the other hand into metaphysics, the theory of ideas, also in Plato. This central position of Anaxagoras is made clear by the passage discussed, according to which, I think, in considering the 'homoiomeries,' we should look upon parts as 'homoiomerous' primarily to the whole i~c6otov, and only secondarily to subordinate wholes. Indeed, it is implied in Anaxagoras' principle that there are only two entities which are properly wholes, the 0c0/cpo and voDv^. To call anything else a whole is more or less arbitrary, a principle not unworthy of the most thorough-going of modern absolutists.

{"_index":"sire","_type":"_doc","_id":"733","_score":null,"_source":{"id":733,"authors_free":[{"id":1096,"entry_id":733,"agent_type":null,"is_normalised":null,"person_id":245,"institution_id":null,"role":{"id":1,"role_name":"author"},"free_name":"Leon, Philip","free_first_name":"Philip","free_last_name":"Leon","norm_person":{"id":245,"first_name":"Philip","last_name":"Leon","full_name":"Leon, Philip","short_ident":"","is_classical_name":null,"dnb_url":"","viaf_url":"","db_url":"","from_claudius":null}}],"entry_title":"The Homoiomeries of Anaxagoras","main_title":{"title":"The Homoiomeries of Anaxagoras"},"abstract":"[Conclusion, p. 141]: Anaxagoras does indeed, as he has been said to do, represent the \r\nculminating point of the enquiry into the one bto-tv. That simple enquiry \r\nfor a simple unity becomes curiously complex, just because of the very \r\nsimplicity and the thorough-going and uncompromising nature of Anaxagoras' \r\nlogical mind. It has with him reached a stage where it must become \r\ntransformed and pass on the one hand into logic in Plato, into the enquiry \r\nabout the nature of predication through Gorgias and Antisthenes, and on the \r\nother hand into metaphysics, the theory of ideas, also in Plato. This central \r\nposition of Anaxagoras is made clear by the passage discussed, according \r\nto which, I think, in considering the 'homoiomeries,' we should look upon \r\nparts as 'homoiomerous' primarily to the whole i~c6otov, and only secondarily \r\nto subordinate wholes. Indeed, it is implied in Anaxagoras' principle that \r\nthere are only two entities which are properly wholes, the 0c0\/cpo and voDv^. To call anything else a whole is more or less arbitrary, a principle not \r\nunworthy of the most thorough-going of modern absolutists. ","btype":3,"date":"1927","language":"English","online_url":"","online_resources":"https:\/\/uni-koeln.sciebo.de\/s\/FXHNwY19loMmfLj","doi_url":null,"categories":[],"authors":[{"id":245,"full_name":"Leon, Philip","role":{"id":1,"role_name":"author"}}],"book":null,"booksection":null,"article":{"id":733,"journal_id":null,"journal_name":"The Classical Quarterly","volume":"21","issue":"3\/4","pages":"133-141"}},"sort":[1927]}

Simplikios, Neplatoniker, 1927
By: Praechter, Karl, Wissowa, Georg (Ed.), Kroll, Wilhelm (Ed.), Mittelhaus, Karl (Ed.)
Eintrag zu Simplikios in der Paulys Realencyclopädie der classischen Altertumswissenschaft

{"_index":"sire","_type":"_doc","_id":"1380","_score":null,"_ignored":["booksection.book.title.keyword"],"_source":{"id":1380,"authors_free":[{"id":2124,"entry_id":1380,"agent_type":"person","is_normalised":1,"person_id":293,"institution_id":null,"role":{"id":1,"role_name":"author"},"free_name":"Praechter, Karl","free_first_name":"Karl","free_last_name":"Praechter","norm_person":{"id":293,"first_name":"Karl","last_name":"Praechter","full_name":"Praechter, Karl","short_ident":"","is_classical_name":null,"dnb_url":"http:\/\/d-nb.info\/gnd\/116278609","viaf_url":"","db_url":"","from_claudius":null}},{"id":2128,"entry_id":1380,"agent_type":"person","is_normalised":1,"person_id":297,"institution_id":null,"role":{"id":2,"role_name":"editor"},"free_name":"Wissowa, Georg","free_first_name":"Georg","free_last_name":"Wissowa","norm_person":{"id":297,"first_name":"Georg","last_name":"Wissowa","full_name":"Wissowa, Georg","short_ident":"","is_classical_name":null,"dnb_url":"http:\/\/d-nb.info\/gnd\/117413755","viaf_url":"","db_url":"","from_claudius":null}},{"id":2129,"entry_id":1380,"agent_type":"person","is_normalised":1,"person_id":300,"institution_id":null,"role":{"id":2,"role_name":"editor"},"free_name":"Kroll, Wilhelm ","free_first_name":"Wilhelm","free_last_name":"Kroll","norm_person":{"id":300,"first_name":"Wilhelm","last_name":"Kroll","full_name":"Kroll, Wilhelm","short_ident":"","is_classical_name":null,"dnb_url":"http:\/\/d-nb.info\/gnd\/116552581","viaf_url":"","db_url":"","from_claudius":null}},{"id":2130,"entry_id":1380,"agent_type":"person","is_normalised":1,"person_id":301,"institution_id":null,"role":{"id":2,"role_name":"editor"},"free_name":"Mittelhaus, Karl","free_first_name":"Karl","free_last_name":"Mittelhaus","norm_person":{"id":301,"first_name":"Karl","last_name":"Mittelhaus","full_name":"Mittelhaus, Karl","short_ident":"","is_classical_name":null,"dnb_url":"http:\/\/d-nb.info\/gnd\/11706355X","viaf_url":"","db_url":"","from_claudius":null}}],"entry_title":"Simplikios, Neplatoniker","main_title":{"title":"Simplikios, Neplatoniker"},"abstract":"Eintrag zu Simplikios in der Paulys Realencyclop\u00e4die der classischen Altertumswissenschaft","btype":2,"date":"1927","language":"German","online_url":"","online_resources":"https:\/\/uni-koeln.sciebo.de\/s\/R4SP66BOfr22vOA","doi_url":null,"categories":[],"authors":[{"id":293,"full_name":"Praechter, Karl","role":{"id":1,"role_name":"author"}},{"id":297,"full_name":"Wissowa, Georg","role":{"id":2,"role_name":"editor"}},{"id":300,"full_name":"Kroll, Wilhelm","role":{"id":2,"role_name":"editor"}},{"id":301,"full_name":"Mittelhaus, Karl","role":{"id":2,"role_name":"editor"}}],"book":null,"booksection":{"id":1380,"section_of":1381,"pages":"204-213","is_catalog":null,"book":{"id":1381,"bilderberg_idno":null,"dare_idno":null,"catalog_idno":null,"entry_type":"reference","type":4,"language":"no language selected","title":"Paulys Realencyclop\u00e4die der classischen Altertumswissenschaft. Neue Bearbeitung begonnen von Georg Wissowa unter Mitwirkung zahlreicher Fachgenossen, herausgegeben von Wilhelm Kroll und Karl Mittelhaus. Zweite Reihe, F\u00fcnfter Halbband: Silacenis bis Sparsus","title_transcript":"","title_translation":"","short_title":"","has_no_author":null,"volume":null,"date":"1927","edition_no":null,"free_date":null,"abstract":"","republication_of":null,"online_url":"","online_resources":"https:\/\/uni-koeln.sciebo.de\/s\/GO1BxyFsBoAXlMx","translation_of":null,"new_edition_of":null,"is_catalog":0,"in_bibliography":0,"is_inactive":0,"notes":null,"doi_url":null,"book":{"id":1381,"pubplace":"Stuttgart","publisher":"Alfred Druckenm\u00fcller Verlag","series":"","volume":"","edition_no":"","valid_from":null,"valid_until":null}}},"article":null},"sort":[1927]}

Simpl. in Aristot. de Caelo p. 370, 29 ff. H, 1924
By: Praechter, Karl
Title Simpl. in Aristot. de Caelo p. 370, 29 ff. H
Type Article
Language German
Date 1924
Journal Hermes
Volume 59
Issue 1
Pages 118-119
Categories no categories
Author(s) Praechter, Karl
Editor(s)
Translator(s)

{"_index":"sire","_type":"_doc","_id":"1477","_score":null,"_source":{"id":1477,"authors_free":[{"id":2558,"entry_id":1477,"agent_type":"person","is_normalised":1,"person_id":293,"institution_id":null,"role":{"id":1,"role_name":"author"},"free_name":"Praechter, Karl","free_first_name":"Karl","free_last_name":"Praechter","norm_person":{"id":293,"first_name":"Karl","last_name":"Praechter","full_name":"Praechter, Karl","short_ident":"","is_classical_name":null,"dnb_url":"http:\/\/d-nb.info\/gnd\/116278609","viaf_url":"","db_url":"","from_claudius":null}}],"entry_title":"Simpl. in Aristot. de Caelo p. 370, 29 ff. H","main_title":{"title":"Simpl. in Aristot. de Caelo p. 370, 29 ff. H"},"abstract":"","btype":3,"date":"1924","language":"German","online_url":"","online_resources":"https:\/\/uni-koeln.sciebo.de\/s\/zc8efUUHCZuTFnA","doi_url":null,"categories":[],"authors":[{"id":293,"full_name":"Praechter, Karl","role":{"id":1,"role_name":"author"}}],"book":null,"booksection":null,"article":{"id":1477,"journal_id":null,"journal_name":"Hermes","volume":"59","issue":"1","pages":"118-119"}},"sort":[1924]}

Nikostratos der Platoniker, 1922
By: Praechter, Karl
Title Nikostratos der Platoniker
Type Article
Language German
Date 1922
Journal Hermes
Volume 57
Issue 4
Pages 481-517
Categories no categories
Author(s) Praechter, Karl
Editor(s)
Translator(s)
Als Beitrag zur Vor- und Entwicklungsgeschichte des Neu­ platonismus auf einem Teilgebiet seiner Lehre möchte [...] die vorliegende Untersuchung betrachtet werden. Ich selbst habe zu zeigen versucht, daß der alexandrinische Neuplatonismus keines­ wegs die Linie Plotin-Porphyrios-Iamblich fortsetzt, sondern an ein früheres Stadium platonischer Lehrentwicklung anschließt. [pp. 516 f.]

{"_index":"sire","_type":"_doc","_id":"775","_score":null,"_source":{"id":775,"authors_free":[{"id":1139,"entry_id":775,"agent_type":null,"is_normalised":null,"person_id":293,"institution_id":null,"role":{"id":1,"role_name":"author"},"free_name":"Praechter, Karl","free_first_name":"Karl","free_last_name":"Praechter","norm_person":{"id":293,"first_name":"Karl","last_name":"Praechter","full_name":"Praechter, Karl","short_ident":"","is_classical_name":null,"dnb_url":"http:\/\/d-nb.info\/gnd\/116278609","viaf_url":"","db_url":"","from_claudius":null}}],"entry_title":"Nikostratos der Platoniker","main_title":{"title":"Nikostratos der Platoniker"},"abstract":"Als Beitrag zur Vor- und Entwicklungsgeschichte des Neu\u00ad\r\nplatonismus auf einem Teilgebiet seiner Lehre m\u00f6chte [...] die \r\nvorliegende Untersuchung betrachtet werden. Ich selbst habe zu \r\nzeigen versucht, da\u00df der alexandrinische Neuplatonismus keines\u00ad\r\nwegs die Linie Plotin-Porphyrios-Iamblich fortsetzt, sondern an ein \r\nfr\u00fcheres Stadium platonischer Lehrentwicklung anschlie\u00dft. [pp. 516 f.]","btype":3,"date":"1922","language":"German","online_url":"","online_resources":"https:\/\/uni-koeln.sciebo.de\/s\/viSBRYmv6qSxA3q","doi_url":null,"categories":[],"authors":[{"id":293,"full_name":"Praechter, Karl","role":{"id":1,"role_name":"author"}}],"book":null,"booksection":null,"article":{"id":775,"journal_id":null,"journal_name":"Hermes","volume":"57","issue":"4","pages":"481-517"}},"sort":[1922]}

Simplicius de anima 146. 21, 1922
By: Shorey, Paul
Title Simplicius de anima 146. 21
Type Article
Language English
Date 1922
Journal Classical Philology
Volume 17
Issue 2
Pages 143-144
Categories no categories
Author(s) Shorey, Paul
Editor(s)
Translator(s)
Note on Simplicius de anima 146. 21

{"_index":"sire","_type":"_doc","_id":"852","_score":null,"_source":{"id":852,"authors_free":[{"id":1256,"entry_id":852,"agent_type":null,"is_normalised":null,"person_id":321,"institution_id":null,"role":{"id":1,"role_name":"author"},"free_name":"Shorey, Paul","free_first_name":"Paul","free_last_name":"Shorey","norm_person":{"id":321,"first_name":"Paul","last_name":"Shorey","full_name":"Shorey, Paul","short_ident":"","is_classical_name":null,"dnb_url":"http:\/\/d-nb.info\/gnd\/101356426X","viaf_url":"","db_url":"","from_claudius":null}}],"entry_title":"Simplicius de anima 146. 21","main_title":{"title":"Simplicius de anima 146. 21"},"abstract":"Note on Simplicius de anima 146. 21","btype":3,"date":"1922","language":"English","online_url":"","online_resources":"https:\/\/uni-koeln.sciebo.de\/s\/AQundZhqjlESI3F","doi_url":null,"categories":[],"authors":[{"id":321,"full_name":"Shorey, Paul","role":{"id":1,"role_name":"author"}}],"book":null,"booksection":null,"article":{"id":852,"journal_id":null,"journal_name":"Classical Philology","volume":"17","issue":"2","pages":"143-144"}},"sort":[1922]}

Ioannes Philoponus, 1917
By: Gudeman, Alfred, Kroll, Wilhelm (Ed.)
Title Ioannes Philoponus
Type Book Section
Language German
Date 1917
Published in Paulys Realencyclopaedie der classischen Altertumswissenschaft. Neunter Band Hyaia — Iugum
Pages 1768-1795
Categories no categories
Author(s) Gudeman, Alfred
Editor(s) Kroll, Wilhelm
Translator(s)

{"_index":"sire","_type":"_doc","_id":"1525","_score":null,"_source":{"id":1525,"authors_free":[{"id":2650,"entry_id":1525,"agent_type":"person","is_normalised":1,"person_id":566,"institution_id":null,"role":{"id":1,"role_name":"author"},"free_name":"Gudeman, Alfred","free_first_name":"Alfred","free_last_name":"Gudeman","norm_person":{"id":566,"first_name":"Alfred","last_name":"Gudeman","full_name":"Gudeman, Alfred","short_ident":"","is_classical_name":null,"dnb_url":"https:\/\/d-nb.info\/gnd\/102810761","viaf_url":"","db_url":"","from_claudius":null}},{"id":2651,"entry_id":1525,"agent_type":"person","is_normalised":1,"person_id":300,"institution_id":null,"role":{"id":2,"role_name":"editor"},"free_name":"Kroll, Wilhelm","free_first_name":"Wilhelm","free_last_name":"Kroll","norm_person":{"id":300,"first_name":"Wilhelm","last_name":"Kroll","full_name":"Kroll, Wilhelm","short_ident":"","is_classical_name":null,"dnb_url":"http:\/\/d-nb.info\/gnd\/116552581","viaf_url":"","db_url":"","from_claudius":null}}],"entry_title":"Ioannes Philoponus","main_title":{"title":"Ioannes Philoponus"},"abstract":"","btype":2,"date":"1917","language":"German","online_url":"","online_resources":"https:\/\/uni-koeln.sciebo.de\/s\/szrAc2uDYBkJaW9","doi_url":null,"categories":[],"authors":[{"id":566,"full_name":"Gudeman, Alfred","role":{"id":1,"role_name":"author"}},{"id":300,"full_name":"Kroll, Wilhelm","role":{"id":2,"role_name":"editor"}}],"book":null,"booksection":{"id":1525,"section_of":1526,"pages":"1768-1795","is_catalog":null,"book":{"id":1526,"bilderberg_idno":null,"dare_idno":null,"catalog_idno":null,"entry_type":"bibliography","type":1,"language":"de","title":"Paulys Realencyclopaedie der classischen Altertumswissenschaft. Neunter Band Hyaia \u2014 Iugum","title_transcript":"","title_translation":"","short_title":"","has_no_author":null,"volume":null,"date":"1916","edition_no":null,"free_date":null,"abstract":"","republication_of":null,"online_url":"","online_resources":"https:\/\/uni-koeln.sciebo.de\/s\/DT7g7hn04BY8jPG","translation_of":null,"new_edition_of":null,"is_catalog":0,"in_bibliography":0,"is_inactive":0,"notes":null,"doi_url":null,"book":{"id":1526,"pubplace":"Stuttgart","publisher":"Metzler","series":"Paulys Realencyclopaedie der classischen Altertumswissenschaft","volume":"9","edition_no":"","valid_from":null,"valid_until":null}}},"article":null},"sort":[1917]}

Paulys Realencyclopaedie der classischen Altertumswissenschaft. Neunter Band Hyaia — Iugum, 1916
By: Kroll, Wilhelm (Ed.)
Title Paulys Realencyclopaedie der classischen Altertumswissenschaft. Neunter Band Hyaia — Iugum
Type Monograph
Language German
Date 1916
Publication Place Stuttgart
Publisher Metzler
Series Paulys Realencyclopaedie der classischen Altertumswissenschaft
Volume 9
Categories no categories
Author(s)
Editor(s) Kroll, Wilhelm
Translator(s)

{"_index":"sire","_type":"_doc","_id":"1526","_score":null,"_source":{"id":1526,"authors_free":[{"id":2652,"entry_id":1526,"agent_type":"person","is_normalised":1,"person_id":300,"institution_id":null,"role":{"id":2,"role_name":"editor"},"free_name":"Kroll, Wilhelm","free_first_name":"Wilhelm","free_last_name":"Kroll","norm_person":{"id":300,"first_name":"Wilhelm","last_name":"Kroll","full_name":"Kroll, Wilhelm","short_ident":"","is_classical_name":null,"dnb_url":"http:\/\/d-nb.info\/gnd\/116552581","viaf_url":"","db_url":"","from_claudius":null}}],"entry_title":"Paulys Realencyclopaedie der classischen Altertumswissenschaft. Neunter Band Hyaia \u2014 Iugum","main_title":{"title":"Paulys Realencyclopaedie der classischen Altertumswissenschaft. Neunter Band Hyaia \u2014 Iugum"},"abstract":"","btype":1,"date":"1916","language":"German","online_url":"","online_resources":"https:\/\/uni-koeln.sciebo.de\/s\/DT7g7hn04BY8jPG","doi_url":null,"categories":[],"authors":[{"id":300,"full_name":"Kroll, Wilhelm","role":{"id":2,"role_name":"editor"}}],"book":{"id":1526,"pubplace":"Stuttgart","publisher":"Metzler","series":"Paulys Realencyclopaedie der classischen Altertumswissenschaft","volume":"9","edition_no":"","valid_from":null,"valid_until":null},"booksection":null,"article":null},"sort":[1916]}

Genethliakon, 1910
By: Robert, Carl (Ed.)
Title Genethliakon
Type Edited Book
Language German
Date 1910
Publication Place Berlin
Publisher Weidmannsche Buchhandlung
Categories no categories
Author(s)
Editor(s) Robert, Carl
Translator(s)
Sammelband mit Aufsätzen zu verschiedenen Themen, Carl Robert von seinen ehemaligen Schülern zu dessem sechzigsten Geburtstag gewidmet.

{"_index":"sire","_type":"_doc","_id":"307","_score":null,"_source":{"id":307,"authors_free":[{"id":385,"entry_id":307,"agent_type":null,"is_normalised":null,"person_id":294,"institution_id":null,"role":{"id":2,"role_name":"editor"},"free_name":"Robert, Carl","free_first_name":"Carl","free_last_name":"Robert","norm_person":{"id":294,"first_name":"Carl","last_name":"Robert","full_name":"Robert, Carl","short_ident":"","is_classical_name":null,"dnb_url":"http:\/\/d-nb.info\/gnd\/116575956","viaf_url":"","db_url":"","from_claudius":null}}],"entry_title":"Genethliakon","main_title":{"title":"Genethliakon"},"abstract":"Sammelband mit Aufs\u00e4tzen zu verschiedenen Themen, Carl Robert von seinen ehemaligen Sch\u00fclern zu dessem sechzigsten Geburtstag gewidmet.","btype":4,"date":"1910","language":"German","online_url":"","online_resources":"https:\/\/uni-koeln.sciebo.de\/s\/dNT1HXFCgRr5Yap","doi_url":null,"categories":[],"authors":[{"id":294,"full_name":"Robert, Carl","role":{"id":2,"role_name":"editor"}}],"book":{"id":307,"pubplace":"Berlin","publisher":"Weidmannsche Buchhandlung","series":"","volume":"","edition_no":"","valid_from":null,"valid_until":null},"booksection":null,"article":null},"sort":[1910]}

Richtungen und Schulen im Neuplatonismus, 1910
By: Praechter, Karl, Robert, Carl (Ed.)
Title Richtungen und Schulen im Neuplatonismus
Type Book Section
Language German
Date 1910
Published in Genethliakon
Pages 105-156
Categories no categories
Author(s) Praechter, Karl
Editor(s) Robert, Carl
Translator(s)
[Conclusion, p. 155]: .Ich fasse zusammen. Die Richtungen innerhalb des Neuplato­ nismus und ihre Verteilung auf die Schulen ergibt folgende Über­ sicht: I. Die Grundlegung des Systems. Plotin und Porphyrios. II. Die spekulative Richtung. Höchste Ausbildung der Meta­ physik, gestützt auf Platon vermittelst eines von lamblich begrün­ deten exegetischen Verfahrens:al Die syrische Schule: lamblich, Theodoros von Asine, De- xippos,b) die athenische Schule: Plutarch, Syrian, Proklos, Damaskios, Simplikios u. a. III. Die religiös-theurgische Richtung: die pergamenischc Schule: Aidesios, Chrysanthios, Eusebios, Maximus, Julian, Eunapios u. a. IV. Die gelehrte Richtung: a) Die Alexandriner: Hypatia, Hierokles, Hermeias, Ammonios, Asklepiodotos, Olympiodor, Philoponos, Elias, David u. a. b) Die Neuplatoniker des Westens: Macrobius, Chalcidius, Boöthius.

{"_index":"sire","_type":"_doc","_id":"1065","_score":null,"_source":{"id":1065,"authors_free":[{"id":1615,"entry_id":1065,"agent_type":null,"is_normalised":null,"person_id":293,"institution_id":null,"role":{"id":1,"role_name":"author"},"free_name":"Praechter, Karl","free_first_name":"Karl","free_last_name":"Praechter","norm_person":{"id":293,"first_name":"Karl","last_name":"Praechter","full_name":"Praechter, Karl","short_ident":"","is_classical_name":null,"dnb_url":"http:\/\/d-nb.info\/gnd\/116278609","viaf_url":"","db_url":"","from_claudius":null}},{"id":1616,"entry_id":1065,"agent_type":null,"is_normalised":null,"person_id":294,"institution_id":null,"role":{"id":2,"role_name":"editor"},"free_name":"Robert, Carl","free_first_name":"Carl","free_last_name":"Robert","norm_person":{"id":294,"first_name":"Carl","last_name":"Robert","full_name":"Robert, Carl","short_ident":"","is_classical_name":null,"dnb_url":"http:\/\/d-nb.info\/gnd\/116575956","viaf_url":"","db_url":"","from_claudius":null}}],"entry_title":"Richtungen und Schulen im Neuplatonismus","main_title":{"title":"Richtungen und Schulen im Neuplatonismus"},"abstract":"[Conclusion, p. 155]: .Ich fasse zusammen. Die Richtungen innerhalb des Neuplato\u00ad\r\nnismus und ihre Verteilung auf die Schulen ergibt folgende \u00dcber\u00ad\r\nsicht:\r\nI. Die Grundlegung des Systems. Plotin und Porphyrios.\r\nII. Die spekulative Richtung. H\u00f6chste Ausbildung der Meta\u00ad\r\nphysik, gest\u00fctzt auf Platon vermittelst eines von lamblich begr\u00fcn\u00ad\r\ndeten exegetischen Verfahrens:al Die syrische Schule: lamblich, Theodoros von Asine, De- \r\nxippos,b) die athenische Schule: Plutarch, Syrian, Proklos, Damaskios, \r\nSimplikios u. a.\r\nIII. Die religi\u00f6s-theurgische Richtung: die pergamenischc Schule: \r\nAidesios, Chrysanthios, Eusebios, Maximus, Julian, Eunapios u. a.\r\nIV. Die gelehrte Richtung:\r\na) Die Alexandriner: Hypatia, Hierokles, Hermeias, Ammonios, \r\nAsklepiodotos, Olympiodor, Philoponos, Elias, David u. a.\r\nb) Die Neuplatoniker des Westens: Macrobius, Chalcidius, \r\nBo\u00f6thius.","btype":2,"date":"1910","language":"German","online_url":"","online_resources":"https:\/\/uni-koeln.sciebo.de\/s\/smPjw1wQbbtz5e9","doi_url":null,"categories":[],"authors":[{"id":293,"full_name":"Praechter, Karl","role":{"id":1,"role_name":"author"}},{"id":294,"full_name":"Robert, Carl","role":{"id":2,"role_name":"editor"}}],"book":null,"booksection":{"id":1065,"section_of":307,"pages":"105-156","is_catalog":null,"book":{"id":307,"bilderberg_idno":null,"dare_idno":null,"catalog_idno":null,"entry_type":null,"type":4,"language":"de","title":"Genethliakon","title_transcript":"","title_translation":"","short_title":"Robert1910","has_no_author":null,"volume":null,"date":"1910","edition_no":null,"free_date":"1910","abstract":"Sammelband mit Aufs\u00e4tzen zu verschiedenen Themen, Carl Robert von seinen ehemaligen Sch\u00fclern zu dessem sechzigsten Geburtstag gewidmet.","republication_of":null,"online_url":"","online_resources":"https:\/\/uni-koeln.sciebo.de\/s\/dNT1HXFCgRr5Yap","translation_of":null,"new_edition_of":null,"is_catalog":0,"in_bibliography":0,"is_inactive":0,"notes":null,"doi_url":null,"book":{"id":307,"pubplace":"Berlin","publisher":"Weidmannsche Buchhandlung","series":"","volume":"","edition_no":"","valid_from":null,"valid_until":null}}},"article":null},"sort":[1910]}

Der Bericht des Simplicius Über die Quadraturen des Antiphon und des Hippokrates, 1907
By: Simplicius, Cilicius, Rudio, Ferdinand (Ed.),
Title Der Bericht des Simplicius Über die Quadraturen des Antiphon und des Hippokrates
Type Monograph
Language German
Date 1907
Publication Place Charleston
Publisher Nabu Press
Categories no categories
Author(s) Simplicius, Cilicius
Editor(s) Rudio, Ferdinand
Translator(s) Rudio, Ferdinand() .
Der Bericlit des Simplicius über die Quadraturen des Antiphon und des Hippokrates ist eine der wichtigsten Quellen für die Geschichte der griechischen Geometrie vor Euklid. Enthält doch dieser Bericht, neben vielen anderen historisch höchst wertvollen Mitteilungen, einen umfangreichen wörtlichen Auszug aus der leider verloren gegangenen Geschichte der Geometrie des Eudemus! Das uns auf diese Weise erhaltene Referat des Eudemus bezieht sich auf die scharfsinnigen Untersuchungen, die Hippokrates von Chios etwa ums Jahr 440 v. Chr. in einer ebenfalls verloren gegangenen Abhandlung über die Quadraturen der sogenannten Möndchen angestellt hat, Untersuchungen, die vielleicht als Vorbereitungen zu der von alters her umworbenen Quadratur des Kreises gedient haben. Die Abhandlung des Hippokrates ist um so wertvoller, als sie die älteste auf griechischem Boden entstandene mathematische Arbeit darstellt, die uns in gesicherter und zugleich ausführlicher und zusammenhängender Überlieferung vorliegt. [introduction]

{"_index":"sire","_type":"_doc","_id":"1423","_score":null,"_source":{"id":1423,"authors_free":[{"id":2233,"entry_id":1423,"agent_type":"person","is_normalised":1,"person_id":62,"institution_id":null,"role":{"id":1,"role_name":"author"},"free_name":"Simplicius, Cilicius","free_first_name":"Cilicius","free_last_name":"Simplicius","norm_person":{"id":62,"first_name":"Cilicius","last_name":"Simplicius ","full_name":"Simplicius Cilicius","short_ident":"","is_classical_name":null,"dnb_url":"http:\/\/d-nb.info\/gnd\/118642421","viaf_url":"","db_url":"","from_claudius":null}},{"id":2234,"entry_id":1423,"agent_type":"person","is_normalised":1,"person_id":407,"institution_id":null,"role":{"id":2,"role_name":"editor"},"free_name":"Rudio, Ferdinand","free_first_name":"Ferdinand","free_last_name":"Rudio","norm_person":{"id":407,"first_name":"Ferdinand","last_name":"Rudio","full_name":"Rudio, Ferdinand","short_ident":"","is_classical_name":null,"dnb_url":"http:\/\/d-nb.info\/gnd\/116670533","viaf_url":"","db_url":"","from_claudius":null}},{"id":2653,"entry_id":1423,"agent_type":"person","is_normalised":null,"person_id":null,"institution_id":null,"role":{"id":3,"role_name":"translator"},"free_name":"Rudio, Ferdinand","free_first_name":"","free_last_name":"","norm_person":null}],"entry_title":"Der Bericht des Simplicius \u00dcber die Quadraturen des Antiphon und des Hippokrates","main_title":{"title":"Der Bericht des Simplicius \u00dcber die Quadraturen des Antiphon und des Hippokrates"},"abstract":"Der Bericlit des Simplicius \u00fcber die Quadraturen des Antiphon und des Hippokrates ist eine der wichtigsten Quellen f\u00fcr die Geschichte der griechischen Geometrie vor Euklid. Enth\u00e4lt doch dieser Bericht, neben vielen anderen historisch h\u00f6chst wertvollen Mitteilungen, einen umfangreichen w\u00f6rtlichen Auszug aus der leider verloren gegangenen Geschichte der Geometrie des Eudemus! Das uns auf diese Weise erhaltene Referat des Eudemus bezieht sich auf die scharfsinnigen Untersuchungen, die Hippokrates von Chios etwa ums Jahr 440 v. Chr. in einer ebenfalls verloren gegangenen Abhandlung \u00fcber die Quadraturen der sogenannten M\u00f6ndchen angestellt hat, Untersuchungen, die vielleicht als Vorbereitungen zu der von alters her umworbenen Quadratur des Kreises gedient haben. Die Abhandlung des Hippokrates ist um so wertvoller, als sie die \u00e4lteste auf griechischem Boden entstandene mathematische Arbeit darstellt, die uns in gesicherter und zugleich ausf\u00fchrlicher und zusammenh\u00e4ngender \u00dcberlieferung vorliegt. [introduction]","btype":1,"date":"1907","language":"German","online_url":"","online_resources":"https:\/\/uni-koeln.sciebo.de\/s\/yrVeMUwJkJZZU4a","doi_url":null,"categories":[],"authors":[{"id":62,"full_name":"Simplicius Cilicius","role":{"id":1,"role_name":"author"}},{"id":407,"full_name":"Rudio, Ferdinand","role":{"id":2,"role_name":"editor"}}],"book":{"id":1423,"pubplace":"Charleston","publisher":"Nabu Press","series":"","volume":"","edition_no":"","valid_from":null,"valid_until":null},"booksection":null,"article":null},"sort":[1907]}

  • PAGE 89 OF 93
War Platons Vorlesung "das Gute" einmalig?, 1968
By: Merlan, Philip
Title War Platons Vorlesung "das Gute" einmalig?
Type Article
Language German
Date 1968
Journal Hermes
Volume 96
Issue 5
Pages 705-709
Categories no categories
Author(s) Merlan, Philip
Editor(s)
Translator(s)
Die  Frage  wurde  kürzlich  von  K räm er  auf  Grund  einer  Sprachanalyse  der 
nunmehr  doch  wohl  jedem  an  griechischer  Philosophie  Interessierten  wohl- 
bekannten  Aristoxenos-Stelle  verneint1.  Im  folgenden  wird  versucht  werden 
zu beweisen,  daß  die  Frage  zu bejahen  ist. [p. 705]

{"_index":"sire","_type":"_doc","_id":"976","_score":null,"_source":{"id":976,"authors_free":[{"id":1475,"entry_id":976,"agent_type":null,"is_normalised":null,"person_id":258,"institution_id":null,"role":{"id":1,"role_name":"author"},"free_name":"Merlan, Philip","free_first_name":"Philip","free_last_name":"Merlan","norm_person":{"id":258,"first_name":"Philip","last_name":"Merlan","full_name":"Merlan, Philip","short_ident":"","is_classical_name":null,"dnb_url":"http:\/\/d-nb.info\/gnd\/128860502","viaf_url":"","db_url":"","from_claudius":null}}],"entry_title":"War Platons Vorlesung \"das Gute\" einmalig?","main_title":{"title":"War Platons Vorlesung \"das Gute\" einmalig?"},"abstract":"Die Frage wurde k\u00fcrzlich von K r\u00e4m er auf Grund einer Sprachanalyse der \r\nnunmehr doch wohl jedem an griechischer Philosophie Interessierten wohl- \r\nbekannten Aristoxenos-Stelle verneint1. Im folgenden wird versucht werden \r\nzu beweisen, da\u00df die Frage zu bejahen ist. [p. 705]","btype":3,"date":"1968","language":"German","online_url":"","online_resources":"https:\/\/uni-koeln.sciebo.de\/s\/kEzwxu6HwXlp903","doi_url":null,"categories":[],"authors":[{"id":258,"full_name":"Merlan, Philip","role":{"id":1,"role_name":"author"}}],"book":null,"booksection":null,"article":{"id":976,"journal_id":null,"journal_name":"Hermes","volume":"96","issue":"5","pages":"705-709"}},"sort":["War Platons Vorlesung \"das Gute\" einmalig?"]}

Wehrli’s Edition of Eudemus of Rhodes: The Physical Fragments from Simplicius’ Commentary On Aristotle’s Physics, 2002
By: Baltussen, Han, Fortenbaugh, William W. (Ed.), Bodnár, István M. (Ed.)
Title Wehrli’s Edition of Eudemus of Rhodes: The Physical Fragments from Simplicius’ Commentary On Aristotle’s Physics
Type Book Section
Language English
Date 2002
Published in Eudemus of Rhodes
Pages 127-156
Categories no categories
Author(s) Baltussen, Han
Editor(s) Fortenbaugh, William W. , Bodnár, István M.
Translator(s)
This text discusses a critical assessment of Wehrli's edition of Eudemus of Rhodes' fragments, focusing on their relevance to physics and Simplicius' commentary on Aristotle's Physics. The author argues that Wehrli's edition, while once standard, no longer meets current standards and necessitates a new one. Simplicius' role in preserving and interpreting ancient philosophers' doctrines and the significance of Eudemus' fragments are highlighted. The paper presents additional passages from Simplicius' commentary that were not included in Wehrli's edition, suggesting the need for a broader approach to studying fragments. The value of Eudemus' clarifications for later commentators is emphasized, leading to the conclusion that a reevaluation of Wehrli's method and form is necessary for future editors of the Eudemian fragments. [introduction/conclusion]

{"_index":"sire","_type":"_doc","_id":"972","_score":null,"_ignored":["booksection.book.abstract.keyword"],"_source":{"id":972,"authors_free":[{"id":1465,"entry_id":972,"agent_type":null,"is_normalised":null,"person_id":39,"institution_id":null,"role":{"id":1,"role_name":"author"},"free_name":"Baltussen, Han","free_first_name":"Han","free_last_name":"Baltussen","norm_person":{"id":39,"first_name":"Han","last_name":"Baltussen","full_name":"Baltussen, Han","short_ident":"","is_classical_name":null,"dnb_url":"http:\/\/d-nb.info\/gnd\/136236456","viaf_url":"","db_url":"","from_claudius":null}},{"id":1466,"entry_id":972,"agent_type":null,"is_normalised":null,"person_id":7,"institution_id":null,"role":{"id":2,"role_name":"editor"},"free_name":"Fortenbaugh, William W.","free_first_name":"William W.","free_last_name":"Fortenbaugh","norm_person":{"id":7,"first_name":"William W. ","last_name":"Fortenbaugh","full_name":"Fortenbaugh, William W. ","short_ident":"","is_classical_name":null,"dnb_url":"http:\/\/d-nb.info\/gnd\/110233700","viaf_url":"","db_url":"","from_claudius":null}},{"id":1467,"entry_id":972,"agent_type":null,"is_normalised":null,"person_id":6,"institution_id":null,"role":{"id":2,"role_name":"editor"},"free_name":"Bodn\u00e1r, Istv\u00e1n M.","free_first_name":"Istv\u00e1n M.","free_last_name":"Bodn\u00e1r","norm_person":{"id":6,"first_name":"Istv\u00e1n M.","last_name":"Bodn\u00e1r","full_name":"Bodn\u00e1r, Istv\u00e1n M.","short_ident":"","is_classical_name":null,"dnb_url":"http:\/\/d-nb.info\/gnd\/1031829717","viaf_url":"","db_url":"","from_claudius":null}}],"entry_title":"Wehrli\u2019s Edition of Eudemus of Rhodes: The Physical Fragments from Simplicius\u2019 Commentary On Aristotle\u2019s Physics","main_title":{"title":"Wehrli\u2019s Edition of Eudemus of Rhodes: The Physical Fragments from Simplicius\u2019 Commentary On Aristotle\u2019s Physics"},"abstract":"This text discusses a critical assessment of Wehrli's edition of Eudemus of Rhodes' fragments, focusing on their relevance to physics and Simplicius' commentary on Aristotle's Physics. The author argues that Wehrli's edition, while once standard, no longer meets current standards and necessitates a new one. Simplicius' role in preserving and interpreting ancient philosophers' doctrines and the significance of Eudemus' fragments are highlighted. The paper presents additional passages from Simplicius' commentary that were not included in Wehrli's edition, suggesting the need for a broader approach to studying fragments. The value of Eudemus' clarifications for later commentators is emphasized, leading to the conclusion that a reevaluation of Wehrli's method and form is necessary for future editors of the Eudemian fragments. [introduction\/conclusion]","btype":2,"date":"2002","language":"English","online_url":"","online_resources":"https:\/\/uni-koeln.sciebo.de\/s\/Owdxxm6uyCqNXiY","doi_url":null,"categories":[],"authors":[{"id":39,"full_name":"Baltussen, Han","role":{"id":1,"role_name":"author"}},{"id":7,"full_name":"Fortenbaugh, William W. ","role":{"id":2,"role_name":"editor"}},{"id":6,"full_name":"Bodn\u00e1r, Istv\u00e1n M.","role":{"id":2,"role_name":"editor"}}],"book":null,"booksection":{"id":972,"section_of":287,"pages":"127-156","is_catalog":null,"book":{"id":287,"bilderberg_idno":null,"dare_idno":null,"catalog_idno":null,"entry_type":null,"type":4,"language":"en","title":"Eudemus of Rhodes","title_transcript":"","title_translation":"","short_title":"Fortenbaugh2002","has_no_author":null,"volume":null,"date":"2002","edition_no":null,"free_date":"2002","abstract":"Eudemus of Rhodes was a pupil of Aristotle in the second half of the fourth century BCE. When Aristotle died, having chosen Theophrastus as his successor, Eudemus returned to Rhodes where it appears he founded his own school. His contributions to logic were significant: he took issue with Aristotle concerning the status of the existential \"is,\" and together with Theophrastus he made important contributions to hypothetical syllogistic and modal logic. He wrote at length on physics, largely following Aristotle, and took an interest in animal behavior. His histories of geometry, arithmetic, and astronomy were of great importance and are responsible for much of what we know of these subjects in earlier times.Volume 11 in the series Rutgers Studies in Classical Humanities is different in that it is composed entirely of articles that discuss Eudemus from a variety of viewpoints. Sixteen scholars representing seven nations have contributed essays to the volume. A special essay by Dimitri Gutas brings together for the first time the Arabic material relating to Eudemus. Other contributors and essays are: Hans B. Gottschalk, \"Eudemus and the Peripatos\"; Tiziano Dorandi, \"Quale aspetto controverso della biografia di Eudemo di Rodi\"; William W. Fortenbaugh, \"Eudemus' Work On Expression\"; Pamela M. Huby, \"Did Aristotle Reply to Eudemus and Theophrastus on Some Logical Issues?\"; Robert Sharples, \"Eudemus Physics: Change, Place and Time\"; Han Baltussen, \"Wehrli's Edition of Eudemus of Rhodes: The Physical Fragments from Simplicius' Commentary on Aristotle's Physics\"; Sylvia Berryman, \"Sumphues and Suneches: Continuity and Coherence in Early Peripatetic Texts\"; Istvbn Bodnbr, \"Eudemus' Unmoved Movers: Fragments 121-123b Wehrli\"; Deborah K. W. Modrak, \"Phantasia, Thought and Science in Eudemus\"; Stephen White, \"Eudemus the Naturalist\"; J orgen Mejer, \"Eudemus and the History of Science\"; Leonid Zhmud, \"Eudemus' History of Mathematics\"; Alan C. Bowen, \"Eudemus' History of Early Greek Astronomy: Two Hypotheses\"; Dmitri Panchenko, \"Eudemus Fr. 145 Wehrli and the Ancient Theories of Lunar Light\"; and Gbbor Betegh, \"On Eudemus Fr. 150 Wehrli.\"\"[Eudemus of Rhodes] marks a substantial progress in our knowledge of Eurdemus. For it enlarges the scope of the information available on this author, highlights the need of, and paves the way to, a new critical edition of the Greek fragments of his works, and provides a clearer view of his life, thought, sources and influence. In all these respects, it represents a necessary complement to Wehrli's edition of Eudemus' fragments.\" -Amos Bertolacci, The Classical BulletinIstvbn Bodnbr is a member of the philosophy department at the Eotvos University in Budapest, where he teaches and does research on ancient philosophy. He has been a junior fellow at the Center for Hellenic Studies and most recently has been an Alexander von Humboldt Stipendiat in Berlin at the Max Plank Institut for Wissenschaftsgeschichte and at the Freie Universitot.William W. Fortenbaugh is professor of classics at Rutgers University. In addition to editing several books in this series, he has written Aristotle on Emotion and Quellen zur Ethik Theophrastus. New is his edition of Theophrastus's treatise On Sweat.","republication_of":null,"online_url":"","online_resources":"https:\/\/uni-koeln.sciebo.de\/s\/Ej9J55UD4Czen6M","translation_of":null,"new_edition_of":null,"is_catalog":0,"in_bibliography":0,"is_inactive":0,"notes":null,"doi_url":null,"book":{"id":287,"pubplace":"New Jersey","publisher":"Transaction Publisher","series":"Rutgers University Studies in Classical Humanities","volume":"11","edition_no":"","valid_from":null,"valid_until":null}}},"article":null},"sort":["Wehrli\u2019s Edition of Eudemus of Rhodes: The Physical Fragments from Simplicius\u2019 Commentary On Aristotle\u2019s Physics"]}

Weltzeiten und Lebenszyklus: Eine Nachprüfung der Empedokles-Doxographie, 1965
By: Hölscher, Uvo
Title Weltzeiten und Lebenszyklus: Eine Nachprüfung der Empedokles-Doxographie
Type Article
Language German
Date 1965
Journal Hermes
Volume 93
Issue 1
Pages 7-33
Categories no categories
Author(s) Hölscher, Uvo
Editor(s)
Translator(s)
Der Text untersucht die Lehre des griechischen Philosophen Empedokles über die periodischen Entstehungs- und Vergehenszyklen der Welt. Es wird diskutiert, dass es bisher keine Einigkeit darüber gibt, wie diese Zyklen im Detail zu verstehen sind. Eine verbreitete Auffassung besagt, dass sich der Zyklus in vier Phasen abspielt, in denen sich jeweils eine Welt bildet, die durch Trennungs- und Vereinigungsprozesse der Elemente entstehen und vergehen. Es wird jedoch argumentiert, dass diese Vorstellung widersprüchlich ist und es keine klare Entscheidung darüber gibt, welche Phase die aktuelle Welt repräsentiert. Der Autor kommt zu dem Schluss, dass die Vorstellung von nur vier Phasen nicht ausreichend ist und dass die Vorstellung eines Ruhezustands der getrennten Elemente unzureichend belegt ist. Stattdessen schlägt der Autor vor, dass es nur zwei Phasen gibt, in denen sich die Kosmogonie und Zoogonie ereignen. [introduction]

{"_index":"sire","_type":"_doc","_id":"1353","_score":null,"_source":{"id":1353,"authors_free":[{"id":2027,"entry_id":1353,"agent_type":"person","is_normalised":1,"person_id":198,"institution_id":null,"role":{"id":1,"role_name":"author"},"free_name":"H\u00f6lscher, Uvo","free_first_name":"Uvo","free_last_name":"H\u00f6lscher","norm_person":{"id":198,"first_name":"Uvo","last_name":"H\u00f6lscher","full_name":"H\u00f6lscher, Uvo","short_ident":"","is_classical_name":null,"dnb_url":"http:\/\/d-nb.info\/gnd\/118705571","viaf_url":"","db_url":"","from_claudius":null}}],"entry_title":"Weltzeiten und Lebenszyklus: Eine Nachpr\u00fcfung der Empedokles-Doxographie","main_title":{"title":"Weltzeiten und Lebenszyklus: Eine Nachpr\u00fcfung der Empedokles-Doxographie"},"abstract":"Der Text untersucht die Lehre des griechischen Philosophen Empedokles \u00fcber die periodischen Entstehungs- und Vergehenszyklen der Welt. Es wird diskutiert, dass es bisher keine Einigkeit dar\u00fcber gibt, wie diese Zyklen im Detail zu verstehen sind. Eine verbreitete Auffassung besagt, dass sich der Zyklus in vier Phasen abspielt, in denen sich jeweils eine Welt bildet, die durch Trennungs- und Vereinigungsprozesse der Elemente entstehen und vergehen. Es wird jedoch argumentiert, dass diese Vorstellung widerspr\u00fcchlich ist und es keine klare Entscheidung dar\u00fcber gibt, welche Phase die aktuelle Welt repr\u00e4sentiert. Der Autor kommt zu dem Schluss, dass die Vorstellung von nur vier Phasen nicht ausreichend ist und dass die Vorstellung eines Ruhezustands der getrennten Elemente unzureichend belegt ist. Stattdessen schl\u00e4gt der Autor vor, dass es nur zwei Phasen gibt, in denen sich die Kosmogonie und Zoogonie ereignen. [introduction]","btype":3,"date":"1965","language":"German","online_url":"","online_resources":"https:\/\/uni-koeln.sciebo.de\/s\/3i3dIX2FiiNPQoT","doi_url":null,"categories":[],"authors":[{"id":198,"full_name":"H\u00f6lscher, Uvo","role":{"id":1,"role_name":"author"}}],"book":null,"booksection":null,"article":{"id":1353,"journal_id":null,"journal_name":"Hermes","volume":"93","issue":"1","pages":"7-33"}},"sort":["Weltzeiten und Lebenszyklus: Eine Nachpr\u00fcfung der Empedokles-Doxographie"]}

Wenn der Steuermann ruft..." (Epiktet, Encheiridion 7), 2022
By: Krämer, Benedikt
Title Wenn der Steuermann ruft..." (Epiktet, Encheiridion 7)
Type Article
Language German
Date 2022
Journal Hyperboreus
Volume 28
Issue 1
Pages 111-122
Categories no categories
Author(s) Krämer, Benedikt
Editor(s)
Translator(s)

{"_index":"sire","_type":"_doc","_id":"1555","_score":null,"_source":{"id":1555,"authors_free":[{"id":2718,"entry_id":1555,"agent_type":"person","is_normalised":null,"person_id":null,"institution_id":null,"role":{"id":1,"role_name":"author"},"free_name":"Kr\u00e4mer, Benedikt","free_first_name":"Benedikt","free_last_name":"Kr\u00e4mer","norm_person":null}],"entry_title":"Wenn der Steuermann ruft...\" (Epiktet, Encheiridion 7)","main_title":{"title":"Wenn der Steuermann ruft...\" (Epiktet, Encheiridion 7)"},"abstract":"","btype":3,"date":"2022","language":"German","online_url":"","online_resources":"https:\/\/uni-koeln.sciebo.de\/s\/CjtWoBp8Z2FqtLn","doi_url":null,"categories":[],"authors":[],"book":null,"booksection":null,"article":{"id":1555,"journal_id":null,"journal_name":"Hyperboreus","volume":"28","issue":"1","pages":"111-122"}},"sort":["Wenn der Steuermann ruft...\" (Epiktet, Encheiridion 7)"]}

Were Aristotle's Intentions in writing the De Anima Forgotten in Late Antiquity?, 1997
By: Blumenthal, Henry J.
Title Were Aristotle's Intentions in writing the De Anima Forgotten in Late Antiquity?
Type Article
Language English
Date 1997
Journal Documenti e Studi sulla Tradizione Filosofica Medievale
Volume 8
Pages 143–157
Categories no categories
Author(s) Blumenthal, Henry J.
Editor(s)
Translator(s)
In general we have to conclude that while the whole "Philoponus” commentary may include a number of explicit references to the biological writings, and while the real Philoponus may often refer to medical and scientific issues, there is no systematic  bias towards explaining the contents of the De anima in terms of them. There is, however, just as in the Ps-Simplicius commentary, enough said about such matters, and 
enough reference made to other parts of the biological corpus, to show that the commentators were still aware of the original intentions of the work — or, at the very least, behaved as if they were — even if they did not always feel bound by them. That awareness was to survive into the Middle Ages as well. [Conclusion, p. 157]

{"_index":"sire","_type":"_doc","_id":"893","_score":null,"_source":{"id":893,"authors_free":[{"id":1316,"entry_id":893,"agent_type":null,"is_normalised":null,"person_id":108,"institution_id":null,"role":{"id":1,"role_name":"author"},"free_name":"Blumenthal, Henry J.","free_first_name":"Henry J.","free_last_name":"Blumenthal","norm_person":{"id":108,"first_name":"Henry J.","last_name":"Blumenthal","full_name":"Blumenthal, Henry J.","short_ident":"","is_classical_name":null,"dnb_url":"http:\/\/d-nb.info\/gnd\/1051543967","viaf_url":"","db_url":"","from_claudius":null}}],"entry_title":"Were Aristotle's Intentions in writing the De Anima Forgotten in Late Antiquity?","main_title":{"title":"Were Aristotle's Intentions in writing the De Anima Forgotten in Late Antiquity?"},"abstract":"In general we have to conclude that while the whole \"Philoponus\u201d commentary may include a number of explicit references to the biological writings, and while the real Philoponus may often refer to medical and scientific issues, there is no systematic bias towards explaining the contents of the De anima in terms of them. There is, however, just as in the Ps-Simplicius commentary, enough said about such matters, and \r\nenough reference made to other parts of the biological corpus, to show that the commentators were still aware of the original intentions of the work \u2014 or, at the very least, behaved as if they were \u2014 even if they did not always feel bound by them. That awareness was to survive into the Middle Ages as well. [Conclusion, p. 157]","btype":3,"date":"1997","language":"English","online_url":"","online_resources":"https:\/\/uni-koeln.sciebo.de\/s\/qhZRe3zhqqbPUeO","doi_url":null,"categories":[],"authors":[{"id":108,"full_name":"Blumenthal, Henry J.","role":{"id":1,"role_name":"author"}}],"book":null,"booksection":null,"article":{"id":893,"journal_id":null,"journal_name":"Documenti e Studi sulla Tradizione Filosofica Medievale","volume":"8","issue":"","pages":"143\u2013157"}},"sort":["Were Aristotle's Intentions in writing the De Anima Forgotten in Late Antiquity?"]}

Were Zeno's Arguments a Reply to Attacks upon Parmenides?, 1957
By: Booth, N.B.
Title Were Zeno's Arguments a Reply to Attacks upon Parmenides?
Type Article
Language English
Date 1957
Journal Phronesis
Volume 2
Issue 1
Pages 1-9
Categories no categories
Author(s) Booth, N.B.
Editor(s)
Translator(s)
This article by N. B. Booth examines whether Zeno's arguments were a response to criticisms of Parmenides's principle „the One“. Despite evidence that Zeno was concerned with defending Parmenides's „One“, his arguments about plurality seem to refute the "ones" of a plurality. One possible explanation is that Zeno's arguments were used to counter criticisms of Parmenides's „One“ before he produced them. Plato's Parmenides includes a passage in which "Zeno" apologizes for his book on plurality, which has been interpreted as an answer to criticisms of Parmenides's theory, but Booth notes that Plato's characters are idealized and it is not certain that Zeno's arguments were a response to attacks. Booth looks at the arguments themselves for evidence and suggests that if some of Zeno's arguments against plural "ones" were valid against Parmenides's „One“, it would be fair to infer that they were used by hostile critics and Zeno was throwing them back in their faces. [introduction]

{"_index":"sire","_type":"_doc","_id":"1127","_score":null,"_source":{"id":1127,"authors_free":[{"id":1702,"entry_id":1127,"agent_type":null,"is_normalised":null,"person_id":10,"institution_id":null,"role":{"id":1,"role_name":"author"},"free_name":"Booth, N.B.","free_first_name":"N.B.","free_last_name":"Booth","norm_person":{"id":10,"first_name":"N. B.","last_name":"Booth","full_name":"Booth, N. B.","short_ident":"","is_classical_name":null,"dnb_url":"","viaf_url":"","db_url":"","from_claudius":null}}],"entry_title":"Were Zeno's Arguments a Reply to Attacks upon Parmenides?","main_title":{"title":"Were Zeno's Arguments a Reply to Attacks upon Parmenides?"},"abstract":"This article by N. B. Booth examines whether Zeno's arguments were a response to criticisms of Parmenides's principle \u201ethe One\u201c. Despite evidence that Zeno was concerned with defending Parmenides's \u201eOne\u201c, his arguments about plurality seem to refute the \"ones\" of a plurality. One possible explanation is that Zeno's arguments were used to counter criticisms of Parmenides's \u201eOne\u201c before he produced them. Plato's Parmenides includes a passage in which \"Zeno\" apologizes for his book on plurality, which has been interpreted as an answer to criticisms of Parmenides's theory, but Booth notes that Plato's characters are idealized and it is not certain that Zeno's arguments were a response to attacks. Booth looks at the arguments themselves for evidence and suggests that if some of Zeno's arguments against plural \"ones\" were valid against Parmenides's \u201eOne\u201c, it would be fair to infer that they were used by hostile critics and Zeno was throwing them back in their faces. [introduction]","btype":3,"date":"1957","language":"English","online_url":"","online_resources":"https:\/\/uni-koeln.sciebo.de\/s\/Z24XRGSFJxejYPK","doi_url":null,"categories":[],"authors":[{"id":10,"full_name":"Booth, N. B.","role":{"id":1,"role_name":"author"}}],"book":null,"booksection":null,"article":{"id":1127,"journal_id":null,"journal_name":"Phronesis","volume":"2","issue":"1","pages":"1-9"}},"sort":["Were Zeno's Arguments a Reply to Attacks upon Parmenides?"]}

What Has Aristotelian Dialectic to Offer a Neoplatonist? A Possible Sample of Iamblichus at Simplicius on the Categories 12,10-13,12, 2012
By: Griffin, Michael J.
Title What Has Aristotelian Dialectic to Offer a Neoplatonist? A Possible Sample of Iamblichus at Simplicius on the Categories 12,10-13,12
Type Article
Language English
Date 2012
Journal The International Journal of the Platonic Tradition
Volume 6
Pages 173-185
Categories no categories
Author(s) Griffin, Michael J.
Editor(s)
Translator(s)
Simplicius in Cat.  12,10-13,12 presents an interesting justifijication for the study of Aristotle’s Categories, based in Neoplatonic psychology and metaphysics. I suggest that this passage could be regarded as a testimonium to Iamblichus’ reasons for endorsing Porphyry’s selection of the Categories as an introductory text of Platonic philosophy. These Iamblichean arguments, richly grounded in Neoplatonic metaphysics and psychology, may have exercised an influence comparable to Porphyry’s. [authors abstract]

{"_index":"sire","_type":"_doc","_id":"937","_score":null,"_source":{"id":937,"authors_free":[{"id":1390,"entry_id":937,"agent_type":null,"is_normalised":null,"person_id":148,"institution_id":null,"role":{"id":1,"role_name":"author"},"free_name":"Griffin, Michael J.","free_first_name":"Michael J.","free_last_name":"Griffin","norm_person":{"id":148,"first_name":"Michael J.","last_name":"Griffin","full_name":"Griffin, Michael J.","short_ident":"","is_classical_name":null,"dnb_url":"http:\/\/d-nb.info\/gnd\/1065676603","viaf_url":"","db_url":"","from_claudius":null}}],"entry_title":"What Has Aristotelian Dialectic to Offer a Neoplatonist? A Possible Sample of Iamblichus at Simplicius on the Categories 12,10-13,12","main_title":{"title":"What Has Aristotelian Dialectic to Offer a Neoplatonist? A Possible Sample of Iamblichus at Simplicius on the Categories 12,10-13,12"},"abstract":"Simplicius in Cat. 12,10-13,12 presents an interesting justif\u0133ication for the study of Aristotle\u2019s Categories, based in Neoplatonic psychology and metaphysics. I suggest that this passage could be regarded as a testimonium to Iamblichus\u2019 reasons for endorsing Porphyry\u2019s selection of the Categories as an introductory text of Platonic philosophy. These Iamblichean arguments, richly grounded in Neoplatonic metaphysics and psychology, may have exercised an influence comparable to Porphyry\u2019s. [authors abstract]","btype":3,"date":"2012","language":"English","online_url":"","online_resources":"https:\/\/uni-koeln.sciebo.de\/s\/OkODIHdy69Gu56Q","doi_url":null,"categories":[],"authors":[{"id":148,"full_name":"Griffin, Michael J.","role":{"id":1,"role_name":"author"}}],"book":null,"booksection":null,"article":{"id":937,"journal_id":null,"journal_name":"The International Journal of the Platonic Tradition","volume":"6","issue":"","pages":"173-185"}},"sort":["What Has Aristotelian Dialectic to Offer a Neoplatonist? A Possible Sample of Iamblichus at Simplicius on the Categories 12,10-13,12"]}

What Is the Principle of Movement, the Self-moved (Plato) or the Unmoved (Aristotle)? The Exegetic Strategies of Hermias of Alexandria and Simplicius in Late Antiquity, 2020
By: Longo, Angela, Finamore, John F. (Ed.), Manolea, Christina-Panagiota (Ed.)
Title What Is the Principle of Movement, the Self-moved (Plato) or the Unmoved (Aristotle)? The Exegetic Strategies of Hermias of Alexandria and Simplicius in Late Antiquity
Type Book Section
Language English
Date 2020
Published in Studies in Hermias’ Commentary on Plato’s Phaedrus
Pages 115-141
Categories no categories
Author(s) Longo, Angela
Editor(s) Finamore, John F. , Manolea, Christina-Panagiota
Translator(s)
In this paper, I will compare Plato’s Phaedrus 245c–e with Aristotle’s Physics
VIII 5. In the Phaedrus passage, Plato describes the soul as that which moves
by itself and therefore is always moving (and hence is immortal), and as the
principle of movement for all moving things. In the Physics chapter, Aristotle assigns the pre-eminent role to that which, among moving things, moves
by itself, and makes the case for the existence of something that moves while
remaining unmoved. This Aristotle regards as the prime mover of all moving
things, including self-moving ones. [introduction]

{"_index":"sire","_type":"_doc","_id":"1486","_score":null,"_ignored":["booksection.book.abstract.keyword"],"_source":{"id":1486,"authors_free":[{"id":2571,"entry_id":1486,"agent_type":"person","is_normalised":1,"person_id":463,"institution_id":null,"role":{"id":1,"role_name":"author"},"free_name":"Longo, Angela","free_first_name":"Angela","free_last_name":"Longo","norm_person":{"id":463,"first_name":"Angela","last_name":"Longo","full_name":"Longo, Angela","short_ident":"","is_classical_name":null,"dnb_url":"http:\/\/d-nb.info\/gnd\/1113305118","viaf_url":"","db_url":"","from_claudius":null}},{"id":2572,"entry_id":1486,"agent_type":"person","is_normalised":1,"person_id":120,"institution_id":null,"role":{"id":2,"role_name":"editor"},"free_name":"Finamore, John F.","free_first_name":"John F.","free_last_name":"Finamore","norm_person":{"id":120,"first_name":"John F.","last_name":"Finamore","full_name":"Finamore, John F.","short_ident":"","is_classical_name":null,"dnb_url":"http:\/\/d-nb.info\/gnd\/1055775080","viaf_url":"","db_url":"","from_claudius":null}},{"id":2573,"entry_id":1486,"agent_type":"person","is_normalised":1,"person_id":551,"institution_id":null,"role":{"id":2,"role_name":"editor"},"free_name":"Manolea, Christina-Panagiota","free_first_name":"Christina-Panagiota","free_last_name":"Manolea","norm_person":{"id":551,"first_name":"Christina-Panagiota","last_name":"Manolea","full_name":"Manolea, Christina-Panagiota","short_ident":"","is_classical_name":null,"dnb_url":"http:\/\/d-nb.info\/gnd\/12962330X","viaf_url":"","db_url":"","from_claudius":null}}],"entry_title":"What Is the Principle of Movement, the Self-moved (Plato) or the Unmoved (Aristotle)? The Exegetic Strategies of Hermias of Alexandria and Simplicius in Late Antiquity","main_title":{"title":"What Is the Principle of Movement, the Self-moved (Plato) or the Unmoved (Aristotle)? The Exegetic Strategies of Hermias of Alexandria and Simplicius in Late Antiquity"},"abstract":"In this paper, I will compare Plato\u2019s Phaedrus 245c\u2013e with Aristotle\u2019s Physics\r\nVIII 5. In the Phaedrus passage, Plato describes the soul as that which moves\r\nby itself and therefore is always moving (and hence is immortal), and as the\r\nprinciple of movement for all moving things. In the Physics chapter, Aristotle assigns the pre-eminent role to that which, among moving things, moves\r\nby itself, and makes the case for the existence of something that moves while\r\nremaining unmoved. This Aristotle regards as the prime mover of all moving\r\nthings, including self-moving ones. [introduction]","btype":2,"date":"2020","language":"English","online_url":"https:\/\/uni-koeln.sciebo.de\/s\/vpMDUPHkT7s2f7i","online_resources":"","doi_url":null,"categories":[],"authors":[{"id":463,"full_name":"Longo, Angela","role":{"id":1,"role_name":"author"}},{"id":120,"full_name":"Finamore, John F.","role":{"id":2,"role_name":"editor"}},{"id":551,"full_name":"Manolea, Christina-Panagiota","role":{"id":2,"role_name":"editor"}}],"book":null,"booksection":{"id":1486,"section_of":1487,"pages":"115-141","is_catalog":null,"book":{"id":1487,"bilderberg_idno":null,"dare_idno":null,"catalog_idno":null,"entry_type":"bibliography","type":4,"language":"en","title":"Studies in Hermias\u2019 Commentary on Plato\u2019s Phaedrus","title_transcript":"","title_translation":"","short_title":"","has_no_author":null,"volume":null,"date":"2019","edition_no":null,"free_date":null,"abstract":"Studies in Hermias\u2019 Commentary on Plato\u2019s Phaedrus is a collection of twelve essays that consider aspects of Hermias\u2019 philosophy, including his notions of the soul, logic, and method of exegesis. The essays also consider Hermias\u2019 work in the tradition of Neoplatonism, particularly in relation to the thought of Iamblichus and Proclus. The collection grapples with the question of the originality of Hermias\u2019 commentary\u2014the only extant work of Hermias\u2014which is a series of lectures notes of his teacher, Syrianus. [author's abstract]","republication_of":null,"online_url":"","online_resources":"https:\/\/uni-koeln.sciebo.de\/s\/odl9mOkFu3fCl3K","translation_of":null,"new_edition_of":null,"is_catalog":0,"in_bibliography":0,"is_inactive":0,"notes":null,"doi_url":null,"book":{"id":1487,"pubplace":"Amsterdam","publisher":"Brill","series":"Studies in Platonism, Neoplatonism, and the Platonic Tradition","volume":"24","edition_no":"","valid_from":null,"valid_until":null}}},"article":null},"sort":["What Is the Principle of Movement, the Self-moved (Plato) or the Unmoved (Aristotle)? The Exegetic Strategies of Hermias of Alexandria and Simplicius in Late Antiquity"]}

What does Aristotle categorize? Semantics and the early peripatetic reading of the "Categories", 2012
By: Griffin, Michael J.
Title What does Aristotle categorize? Semantics and the early peripatetic reading of the "Categories"
Type Article
Language English
Date 2012
Journal Bulletin of the Institute of Classical Studies
Volume 55
Issue 1
Pages 69-108
Categories no categories
Author(s) Griffin, Michael J.
Editor(s)
Translator(s)
One of the more provocative mysteries of later ancient philosophy is how Porphyiy came 
to situate the Categories of Aristotle at the outset of the nascent Neoplatonic curriculum.
After all, the Categories tends to strike modem readers as a temperamentally counter-Platonic work, in which Aristotle grants ontological priority to perceptible subjects over intelligible genera and species,  and we are led to wonder how a Platonist would be 
motivated to encourage its use as a general introduction to philosophy. The commentary 
tradition has left us with several  layers of evidence for Porphyry's reasoning. First, in answer to the general question  "Why should a philosopher study the Categories?" we have 
Porphyry's assertion that the ten Aristotelian schemata of predication carve the genera of 
being accurately at the joints (in Cat. 58,5-59,33), that this isomorphism between kind of simple referring terms and kinds of beings facilitates human knowledge, and that the 
philosopher's path therefore begins from the correct inteipretation of the Categories (see for example T9-11, discussed below). Second, in response to the question 'Why is the Categories compatible with Platonism?’, we have Porphyry’s account that the Categories introduces the student to the study of referring terms, which refer primarily to perceptible beings;  after  we  have  grasped  the  correct  application  of  language  to  perceptibles, 
however, we are prepared to 'ascend by analogy’ to the study of intelligibles, which is 
Plato’s ambit.  But this pedagogical  solution,  while  it jibes  elegantly with  Porphyry!s 
decision to bracket metaphysical questions from introductory logic {cf. Isagoge 4,10-15, with Barnes 2003 ad loc.), also suggests a tension between two layers of Porphyry’s thought about die Categories. On the one hand, we are motivated to read the treatise 
because its divisions ofmeaningful language exhaustively and accurately picture being; on  the  other hand,  we  acknowledge that the text has nothing to  say about die most important kind of being, namely intelligible being.  In other words, Porphyry’s leading 
argument  in  favour  of studying  the  Categories (its comprehensiveness)  seems  like a strange bedfellow for his leading argument in favour of its compatibility with Platonism 
(its restrictedness); and the source of this general tension is the first puzzle that I would like to explore in this essay. [Introduction, pp. 69 f.]

{"_index":"sire","_type":"_doc","_id":"1148","_score":null,"_source":{"id":1148,"authors_free":[{"id":1723,"entry_id":1148,"agent_type":null,"is_normalised":null,"person_id":148,"institution_id":null,"role":{"id":1,"role_name":"author"},"free_name":"Griffin, Michael J.","free_first_name":"Michael J.","free_last_name":"Griffin","norm_person":{"id":148,"first_name":"Michael J.","last_name":"Griffin","full_name":"Griffin, Michael J.","short_ident":"","is_classical_name":null,"dnb_url":"http:\/\/d-nb.info\/gnd\/1065676603","viaf_url":"","db_url":"","from_claudius":null}}],"entry_title":"What does Aristotle categorize? Semantics and the early peripatetic reading of the \"Categories\"","main_title":{"title":"What does Aristotle categorize? Semantics and the early peripatetic reading of the \"Categories\""},"abstract":"One of the more provocative mysteries of later ancient philosophy is how Porphyiy came \r\nto situate the Categories of Aristotle at the outset of the nascent Neoplatonic curriculum.\r\nAfter all, the Categories tends to strike modem readers as a temperamentally counter-Platonic work, in which Aristotle grants ontological priority to perceptible subjects over intelligible genera and species, and we are led to wonder how a Platonist would be \r\nmotivated to encourage its use as a general introduction to philosophy. The commentary \r\ntradition has left us with several layers of evidence for Porphyry's reasoning. First, in answer to the general question \"Why should a philosopher study the Categories?\" we have \r\nPorphyry's assertion that the ten Aristotelian schemata of predication carve the genera of \r\nbeing accurately at the joints (in Cat. 58,5-59,33), that this isomorphism between kind of simple referring terms and kinds of beings facilitates human knowledge, and that the \r\nphilosopher's path therefore begins from the correct inteipretation of the Categories (see for example T9-11, discussed below). Second, in response to the question 'Why is the Categories compatible with Platonism?\u2019, we have Porphyry\u2019s account that the Categories introduces the student to the study of referring terms, which refer primarily to perceptible beings; after we have grasped the correct application of language to perceptibles, \r\nhowever, we are prepared to 'ascend by analogy\u2019 to the study of intelligibles, which is \r\nPlato\u2019s ambit. But this pedagogical solution, while it jibes elegantly with Porphyry!s \r\ndecision to bracket metaphysical questions from introductory logic {cf. Isagoge 4,10-15, with Barnes 2003 ad loc.), also suggests a tension between two layers of Porphyry\u2019s thought about die Categories. On the one hand, we are motivated to read the treatise \r\nbecause its divisions ofmeaningful language exhaustively and accurately picture being; on the other hand, we acknowledge that the text has nothing to say about die most important kind of being, namely intelligible being. In other words, Porphyry\u2019s leading \r\nargument in favour of studying the Categories (its comprehensiveness) seems like a strange bedfellow for his leading argument in favour of its compatibility with Platonism \r\n(its restrictedness); and the source of this general tension is the first puzzle that I would like to explore in this essay. [Introduction, pp. 69 f.]","btype":3,"date":"2012","language":"English","online_url":"","online_resources":"https:\/\/uni-koeln.sciebo.de\/s\/E7XiS12GrRNsPr9","doi_url":null,"categories":[],"authors":[{"id":148,"full_name":"Griffin, Michael J.","role":{"id":1,"role_name":"author"}}],"book":null,"booksection":null,"article":{"id":1148,"journal_id":null,"journal_name":"Bulletin of the Institute of Classical Studies","volume":"55","issue":"1","pages":"69-108"}},"sort":["What does Aristotle categorize? Semantics and the early peripatetic reading of the \"Categories\""]}

What goes up: Proclus against Aristotle on the fifth element, 2002
By: Baltzly, Dirk
Title What goes up: Proclus against Aristotle on the fifth element
Type Article
Language English
Date 2002
Journal Australasian Journal of Philosophy
Volume 80
Issue 3
Pages 261-287
Categories no categories
Author(s) Baltzly, Dirk
Editor(s)
Translator(s)
In this paper, I consider Proclus’ arguments against Aristotle on the composition of the 
heavens from the fifth element, the aether. Proclus argues for the Platonic view (Timaeus 
40a) that the heavenly bodies are composed of all four elements, with fire predominating. 
I think that his discussion exhibits all the methodological features that we find admirable 
in  Aristotle’s  largely  a priori  proto-science.  Proclus’  treatment  of the  question  in  his 
commentary  on  Plato’s  Timaeus  also  provides  the  fullest  statement  of a  neoplatonic 
alternative to the Aristotelian theory of the elements. As such, it forms a significant part of 
a  still  largely underappreciated neoplatonic  legacy to  the history of science. [authors abstract]

{"_index":"sire","_type":"_doc","_id":"962","_score":null,"_source":{"id":962,"authors_free":[{"id":1444,"entry_id":962,"agent_type":null,"is_normalised":null,"person_id":107,"institution_id":null,"role":{"id":1,"role_name":"author"},"free_name":"Baltzly, Dirk","free_first_name":"Dirk","free_last_name":"Baltzly","norm_person":{"id":107,"first_name":"Dirk","last_name":"Baltzly","full_name":"Baltzly, Dirk","short_ident":"","is_classical_name":null,"dnb_url":"http:\/\/d-nb.info\/gnd\/1150414960","viaf_url":"","db_url":"","from_claudius":null}}],"entry_title":"What goes up: Proclus against Aristotle on the fifth element","main_title":{"title":"What goes up: Proclus against Aristotle on the fifth element"},"abstract":"In this paper, I consider Proclus\u2019 arguments against Aristotle on the composition of the \r\nheavens from the fifth element, the aether. Proclus argues for the Platonic view (Timaeus \r\n40a) that the heavenly bodies are composed of all four elements, with fire predominating. \r\nI think that his discussion exhibits all the methodological features that we find admirable \r\nin Aristotle\u2019s largely a priori proto-science. Proclus\u2019 treatment of the question in his \r\ncommentary on Plato\u2019s Timaeus also provides the fullest statement of a neoplatonic \r\nalternative to the Aristotelian theory of the elements. As such, it forms a significant part of \r\na still largely underappreciated neoplatonic legacy to the history of science. [authors abstract]","btype":3,"date":"2002","language":"English","online_url":"","online_resources":"https:\/\/uni-koeln.sciebo.de\/s\/M34EGiOeJdMYBkH","doi_url":null,"categories":[],"authors":[{"id":107,"full_name":"Baltzly, Dirk","role":{"id":1,"role_name":"author"}}],"book":null,"booksection":null,"article":{"id":962,"journal_id":null,"journal_name":"Australasian Journal of Philosophy","volume":"80","issue":"3","pages":"261-287"}},"sort":["What goes up: Proclus against Aristotle on the fifth element"]}

  • PAGE 89 OF 93