Title | Aristotle De Caelo 288a 2-9 |
Type | Article |
Language | English |
Date | 1939 |
Journal | The Classical Quarterly |
Volume | 33 |
Issue | 1 |
Pages | 34-35 |
Categories | no categories |
Author(s) | Cornford, Francis Macdonald |
Editor(s) | |
Translator(s) |
In this passage from Aristotle's De Caelo, he explores why the heavens revolve in one direction rather than the other. He suggests that the universe has a front and a back, which implies a forward motion that is superior to backward motion, just as upward and rightward motions are superior to their respective opposites. Aristotle argues that since nature always follows the best course, the direction of the heaven's revolution must be forward and therefore better. The text is difficult to understand due to possible corruptions, but a comparison with Simplicius' paraphrase suggests that both the subject and object of the main verb are missing and need to be restored. [introduction/conclusion] |
Online Resources | https://uni-koeln.sciebo.de/s/NfJMuZWhRJUPSCS |
{"_index":"sire","_type":"_doc","_id":"1281","_score":null,"_source":{"id":1281,"authors_free":[{"id":1870,"entry_id":1281,"agent_type":"person","is_normalised":1,"person_id":55,"institution_id":null,"role":{"id":1,"role_name":"author"},"free_name":"Cornford, Francis Macdonald","free_first_name":"Francis Macdonald","free_last_name":"Cornford","norm_person":{"id":55,"first_name":"Francis Macdonald","last_name":"Cornford","full_name":"Cornford, Francis Macdonald","short_ident":"","is_classical_name":null,"dnb_url":"http:\/\/d-nb.info\/gnd\/118975056","viaf_url":"","db_url":"","from_claudius":null}}],"entry_title":"Aristotle De Caelo 288a 2-9","main_title":{"title":"Aristotle De Caelo 288a 2-9"},"abstract":"In this passage from Aristotle's De Caelo, he explores why the heavens revolve in one direction rather than the other. He suggests that the universe has a front and a back, which implies a forward motion that is superior to backward motion, just as upward and rightward motions are superior to their respective opposites. Aristotle argues that since nature always follows the best course, the direction of the heaven's revolution must be forward and therefore better. The text is difficult to understand due to possible corruptions, but a comparison with Simplicius' paraphrase suggests that both the subject and object of the main verb are missing and need to be restored. [introduction\/conclusion]","btype":3,"date":"1939","language":"English","online_url":"","online_resources":"https:\/\/uni-koeln.sciebo.de\/s\/NfJMuZWhRJUPSCS","doi_url":null,"categories":[],"authors":[{"id":55,"full_name":"Cornford, Francis Macdonald","role":{"id":1,"role_name":"author"}}],"book":null,"booksection":null,"article":{"id":1281,"journal_id":null,"journal_name":"The Classical Quarterly","volume":"33","issue":"1","pages":"34-35"}},"sort":[1939]}
Title | Der Satz des Anaximandros von Milet (VS⁵ 12 B 1) |
Type | Article |
Language | German |
Date | 1938 |
Journal | Rheinisches Museum für Philologie |
Volume | 87 |
Issue | 4 |
Pages | 376-382 |
Categories | no categories |
Author(s) | Dirlmeier, Franz |
Editor(s) | |
Translator(s) |
Die Weltsicht der Ionier wird zu einer Zeit, als sie schon der Geschichte angehörte, neu geformt durch die Wissenschaft- ler der aristotelischen Schule, die somit die uranfängliche Scheu vor dem Unbestimmten, Unbegrenzten treu bewahren. Aber sie dehnen sie auch noch aus auf fast alle Bereiche des Seins. Frühionische Bändigung des Chaos der -feveffeic in irepioboi vollzieht sich aufs neue, wenn etwa Aristoteles den ungeord- neten, den nur „gereihten46 Ablauf der Menschenrede „unter- wirft", mit der Begründung: die XéHiç elpojiévTi sei ein àr'bkç olà tò ÔTreipov tò fàp TéXoç iravreç ßouXovrai K0t6opâv (Rhet. y 9, 1409 a31). Wenn wir zu den Erkenntnissen der schöpferischen Jahrhunderte VI bis III die sorgsame Auseinandersetzung des Simplikios nehmen, der am Ausgang der Antike mit fester Hand das gültig Gedachte noch einmal zusammenfaßt, so haben wir damit ein Jahrtausend hellenischen Geistes überblickt. [p. 382] |
Online Resources | https://uni-koeln.sciebo.de/s/GvW8g50PoxkFsCo |
{"_index":"sire","_type":"_doc","_id":"757","_score":null,"_source":{"id":757,"authors_free":[{"id":1122,"entry_id":757,"agent_type":null,"is_normalised":null,"person_id":63,"institution_id":null,"role":{"id":1,"role_name":"author"},"free_name":"Dirlmeier, Franz ","free_first_name":"Franz","free_last_name":"Dirlmeier","norm_person":{"id":63,"first_name":"Franz ","last_name":"Dirlmeier","full_name":"Dirlmeier, Franz ","short_ident":"","is_classical_name":null,"dnb_url":"http:\/\/d-nb.info\/gnd\/140255591","viaf_url":"","db_url":"","from_claudius":null}}],"entry_title":"Der Satz des Anaximandros von Milet (VS\u2075 12 B 1)","main_title":{"title":"Der Satz des Anaximandros von Milet (VS\u2075 12 B 1)"},"abstract":"Die Weltsicht der Ionier wird zu einer Zeit, als sie schon \r\nder Geschichte angeh\u00f6rte, neu geformt durch die Wissenschaft- \r\nler der aristotelischen Schule, die somit die uranf\u00e4ngliche Scheu \r\nvor dem Unbestimmten, Unbegrenzten treu bewahren. Aber \r\nsie dehnen sie auch noch aus auf fast alle Bereiche des Seins. \r\nFr\u00fchionische B\u00e4ndigung des Chaos der -feveffeic in irepioboi \r\nvollzieht sich aufs neue, wenn etwa Aristoteles den ungeord- \r\nneten, den nur \u201egereihten46 Ablauf der Menschenrede \u201eunter- \r\nwirft\", mit der Begr\u00fcndung: die X\u00e9Hi\u00e7 elpoji\u00e9vTi sei ein \u00e0r'bk\u00e7 ol\u00e0 \r\nt\u00f2 \u00d4Treipov t\u00f2 f\u00e0p T\u00e9Xo\u00e7 iravre\u00e7 \u00dfouXovrai K0t6op\u00e2v (Rhet. y 9, \r\n1409 a31). Wenn wir zu den Erkenntnissen der sch\u00f6pferischen \r\nJahrhunderte VI bis III die sorgsame Auseinandersetzung des \r\nSimplikios nehmen, der am Ausgang der Antike mit fester Hand \r\ndas g\u00fcltig Gedachte noch einmal zusammenfa\u00dft, so haben \r\nwir damit ein Jahrtausend hellenischen Geistes \u00fcberblickt. [p. 382]","btype":3,"date":"1938","language":"German","online_url":"","online_resources":"https:\/\/uni-koeln.sciebo.de\/s\/GvW8g50PoxkFsCo","doi_url":null,"categories":[],"authors":[{"id":63,"full_name":"Dirlmeier, Franz ","role":{"id":1,"role_name":"author"}}],"book":null,"booksection":null,"article":{"id":757,"journal_id":null,"journal_name":"Rheinisches Museum f\u00fcr Philologie","volume":"87","issue":"4","pages":"376-382"}},"sort":[1938]}
Title | Indivisible Lines |
Type | Article |
Language | English |
Date | 1936 |
Journal | The Classical Quarterly |
Volume | 30 |
Issue | 2 |
Pages | 120-126 |
Categories | no categories |
Author(s) | Nicol, A. T. |
Editor(s) | |
Translator(s) |
The name of Democritus can claim a place in any discussion of indivisibles. Yet its introduction in this paper seems to depend on the lucus a non lucendo principle ; for Democritus did not believe in the existence of indivisible lines. Nowhere is the belief ascribed to him and in at least one place it is implicitly denied, the scholion on De Caelo 268a x, which says he made his elements indivisible solids, as contrasted with lines or surfaces. Two passages, one from Plutarch, the other from Simplicius, will show why he could not believe in indivisible lines. [p. 120] |
Online Resources | https://uni-koeln.sciebo.de/s/j7CSmqxKwIBye6i |
{"_index":"sire","_type":"_doc","_id":"866","_score":null,"_source":{"id":866,"authors_free":[{"id":1270,"entry_id":866,"agent_type":null,"is_normalised":null,"person_id":278,"institution_id":null,"role":{"id":1,"role_name":"author"},"free_name":"Nicol, A. T.","free_first_name":"A. T.","free_last_name":"Nicol","norm_person":{"id":278,"first_name":"Nicol","last_name":"A. T.","full_name":"Nicol, A. T.","short_ident":"","is_classical_name":null,"dnb_url":"","viaf_url":"","db_url":"","from_claudius":null}}],"entry_title":"Indivisible Lines","main_title":{"title":"Indivisible Lines"},"abstract":"The name of Democritus can claim a place in any discussion of indivisibles. \r\nYet its introduction in this paper seems to depend on the lucus a non lucendo principle ; \r\nfor Democritus did not believe in the existence of indivisible lines. Nowhere is the \r\nbelief ascribed to him and in at least one place it is implicitly denied, the scholion on \r\nDe Caelo 268a x, which says he made his elements indivisible solids, as contrasted \r\nwith lines or surfaces. Two passages, one from Plutarch, the other from Simplicius, will show why he could not believe in indivisible lines. [p. 120]","btype":3,"date":"1936","language":"English","online_url":"","online_resources":"https:\/\/uni-koeln.sciebo.de\/s\/j7CSmqxKwIBye6i","doi_url":null,"categories":[],"authors":[{"id":278,"full_name":"Nicol, A. T.","role":{"id":1,"role_name":"author"}}],"book":null,"booksection":null,"article":{"id":866,"journal_id":null,"journal_name":"The Classical Quarterly","volume":"30","issue":"2","pages":"120-126"}},"sort":[1936]}
Title | A New Fragment of Parmenides |
Type | Article |
Language | English |
Date | 1935 |
Journal | The Classical Review |
Volume | 49 |
Issue | 4 |
Pages | 122-123 |
Categories | no categories |
Author(s) | Cornford, Francis Macdonald |
Editor(s) | |
Translator(s) |
The text discusses a disputed line in Parmenides, quoted in Plato's Theaetetus and Simplicius' Physics. Some editors deny the line's independent existence, claiming it was created by Plato by misquoting another verse. The author disagrees with this view, arguing that the line is meaningful and could have been in their texts of Parmenides. The author also argues that there is no reason to believe that Simplicius took the line from Plato, and that Plato was not slovenly in his treatment of Parmenides. The author proposes a corrected version of the line and suggests that it may be Parmenides' last word on the unity and unchangeableness of Being. [introduction/conclusion] |
Online Resources | https://uni-koeln.sciebo.de/s/22AiAGR3zgXhXHY |
{"_index":"sire","_type":"_doc","_id":"1280","_score":null,"_source":{"id":1280,"authors_free":[{"id":1869,"entry_id":1280,"agent_type":"person","is_normalised":1,"person_id":55,"institution_id":null,"role":{"id":1,"role_name":"author"},"free_name":"Cornford, Francis Macdonald","free_first_name":"Francis Macdonald","free_last_name":"Cornford","norm_person":{"id":55,"first_name":"Francis Macdonald","last_name":"Cornford","full_name":"Cornford, Francis Macdonald","short_ident":"","is_classical_name":null,"dnb_url":"http:\/\/d-nb.info\/gnd\/118975056","viaf_url":"","db_url":"","from_claudius":null}}],"entry_title":"A New Fragment of Parmenides","main_title":{"title":"A New Fragment of Parmenides"},"abstract":"The text discusses a disputed line in Parmenides, quoted in Plato's Theaetetus and Simplicius' Physics. Some editors deny the line's independent existence, claiming it was created by Plato by misquoting another verse. The author disagrees with this view, arguing that the line is meaningful and could have been in their texts of Parmenides. The author also argues that there is no reason to believe that Simplicius took the line from Plato, and that Plato was not slovenly in his treatment of Parmenides. The author proposes a corrected version of the line and suggests that it may be Parmenides' last word on the unity and unchangeableness of Being. [introduction\/conclusion]","btype":3,"date":"1935","language":"English","online_url":"","online_resources":"https:\/\/uni-koeln.sciebo.de\/s\/22AiAGR3zgXhXHY","doi_url":null,"categories":[],"authors":[{"id":55,"full_name":"Cornford, Francis Macdonald","role":{"id":1,"role_name":"author"}}],"book":null,"booksection":null,"article":{"id":1280,"journal_id":null,"journal_name":"The Classical Review","volume":"49","issue":"4","pages":"122-123"}},"sort":[1935]}
Title | Ein Simplikios-Zitat bei Pseudo-Alexandros und ein Plotinos-Zitat bei Simplikios |
Type | Article |
Language | German |
Date | 1935 |
Journal | Rheinisches Museum für Philologie. Neue Folge |
Volume | 84 |
Issue | 2 |
Pages | 154-160 |
Categories | no categories |
Author(s) | Merlan, Philipp |
Editor(s) | |
Translator(s) |
In diesem Text geht es um Simplikios' Kommentar zu Aristoteles' De caelo II, 1, 284 a 14 ff. und Pseudo-Alexandros' Kommentar zu Aristoteles' Metaphysik A, 8, 1074aff. Beide diskutieren Fragen zur Bewegung des Himmels und stellen ähnliche Gedanken zum Verhältnis von Seele und Bewegung dar. Der Text betrachtet die Möglichkeit, dass Simplikios und Pseudo-Alexandros einander zitiert haben oder dass sie beide den echten Alexandros zitieren. Es wird auch auf die Interpretation von Aristoteles' De caelo H, 1,284a 27 ff. durch Simplikios eingegangen. [whole text] |
Online Resources | https://uni-koeln.sciebo.de/s/7lVxYR3sHQ2Ie0a |
{"_index":"sire","_type":"_doc","_id":"1209","_score":null,"_source":{"id":1209,"authors_free":[{"id":1790,"entry_id":1209,"agent_type":null,"is_normalised":null,"person_id":258,"institution_id":null,"role":{"id":1,"role_name":"author"},"free_name":"Merlan, Philipp","free_first_name":"Philipp","free_last_name":"Merlan","norm_person":{"id":258,"first_name":"Philip","last_name":"Merlan","full_name":"Merlan, Philip","short_ident":"","is_classical_name":null,"dnb_url":"http:\/\/d-nb.info\/gnd\/128860502","viaf_url":"","db_url":"","from_claudius":null}}],"entry_title":"Ein Simplikios-Zitat bei Pseudo-Alexandros und ein Plotinos-Zitat bei Simplikios","main_title":{"title":"Ein Simplikios-Zitat bei Pseudo-Alexandros und ein Plotinos-Zitat bei Simplikios"},"abstract":"In diesem Text geht es um Simplikios' Kommentar zu Aristoteles' De caelo II, 1, 284 a 14 ff. und Pseudo-Alexandros' Kommentar zu Aristoteles' Metaphysik A, 8, 1074aff. Beide diskutieren Fragen zur Bewegung des Himmels und stellen \u00e4hnliche Gedanken zum Verh\u00e4ltnis von Seele und Bewegung dar. Der Text betrachtet die M\u00f6glichkeit, dass Simplikios und Pseudo-Alexandros einander zitiert haben oder dass sie beide den echten Alexandros zitieren. Es wird auch auf die Interpretation von Aristoteles' De caelo H, 1,284a 27 ff. durch Simplikios eingegangen. [whole text]","btype":3,"date":"1935","language":"German","online_url":"","online_resources":"https:\/\/uni-koeln.sciebo.de\/s\/7lVxYR3sHQ2Ie0a","doi_url":null,"categories":[],"authors":[{"id":258,"full_name":"Merlan, Philip","role":{"id":1,"role_name":"author"}}],"book":null,"booksection":null,"article":{"id":1209,"journal_id":null,"journal_name":"Rheinisches Museum f\u00fcr Philologie. Neue Folge","volume":"84","issue":"2","pages":"154-160"}},"sort":[1935]}
Title | Zur Entstehung und zum Wesen des griechischen wissenschaftlichen Kommentars |
Type | Article |
Language | German |
Date | 1932 |
Journal | Hermes |
Volume | 67 |
Issue | 4 |
Pages | 397-412 |
Categories | no categories |
Author(s) | Geffcken, Johannes |
Editor(s) | |
Translator(s) |
In dem Text wird die Entstehung und das Wesen des antiken Kommentars untersucht. Es wird aufgezeigt, dass der Kommentar in der Antike als eine Art praktische Notwendigkeit angesehen wurde, sei es in Form von Erklärungen zu sakralen Gesetzen, Schulunterricht oder Homerparaphrasen. Die Aristotelische Schule beeinflusste den Geist aller wissenschaftlichen Kommentare. Der Autor schlägt vor, dass eine wirkliche Geschichte des antiken Kommentars notwendig ist, um die Kontinuität und die individuellen Beiträge der Forscher und Denker zu verstehen. [introduction/conclusion] |
Online Resources | https://uni-koeln.sciebo.de/s/lev9vfokt9KpzHD |
{"_index":"sire","_type":"_doc","_id":"1314","_score":null,"_source":{"id":1314,"authors_free":[{"id":1948,"entry_id":1314,"agent_type":"person","is_normalised":1,"person_id":126,"institution_id":null,"role":{"id":1,"role_name":"author"},"free_name":"Geffcken, Johannes","free_first_name":"Johannes","free_last_name":"Geffcken","norm_person":{"id":126,"first_name":"Johannes","last_name":"Geffcken","full_name":"Geffcken, Johannes","short_ident":"","is_classical_name":null,"dnb_url":"http:\/\/d-nb.info\/gnd\/120376644","viaf_url":"","db_url":"","from_claudius":null}}],"entry_title":"Zur Entstehung und zum Wesen des griechischen wissenschaftlichen Kommentars","main_title":{"title":"Zur Entstehung und zum Wesen des griechischen wissenschaftlichen Kommentars"},"abstract":"In dem Text wird die Entstehung und das Wesen des antiken Kommentars untersucht. Es wird aufgezeigt, dass der Kommentar in der Antike als eine Art praktische Notwendigkeit angesehen wurde, sei es in Form von Erkl\u00e4rungen zu sakralen Gesetzen, Schulunterricht oder Homerparaphrasen. Die Aristotelische Schule beeinflusste den Geist aller wissenschaftlichen Kommentare. Der Autor schl\u00e4gt vor, dass eine wirkliche Geschichte des antiken Kommentars notwendig ist, um die Kontinuit\u00e4t und die individuellen Beitr\u00e4ge der Forscher und Denker zu verstehen. [introduction\/conclusion]","btype":3,"date":"1932","language":"German","online_url":"","online_resources":"https:\/\/uni-koeln.sciebo.de\/s\/lev9vfokt9KpzHD","doi_url":null,"categories":[],"authors":[{"id":126,"full_name":"Geffcken, Johannes","role":{"id":1,"role_name":"author"}}],"book":null,"booksection":null,"article":{"id":1314,"journal_id":null,"journal_name":"Hermes","volume":"67","issue":"4","pages":"397-412"}},"sort":[1932]}
Title | The Parmenides of Plato and the Origin of the Neoplatonic 'One' |
Type | Article |
Language | English |
Date | 1928 |
Journal | Classical Quarterly |
Volume | 22 |
Issue | 3/4 (Jul. - Oct., 1928), |
Pages | 129–142 |
Categories | no categories |
Author(s) | Dodds, Eric R. |
Editor(s) | |
Translator(s) |
THE last phase of Greek philosophy has until recently been less intelli- gently studied than any other, and in our understanding of its development there are still lamentable lacunae. Three errors in particular have in the past prevented a proper appreciation of Plotinus' place in the history of philosophy. When this false trail was at length abandoned the fashion for orientalizing explanations persisted in another guise: to the earliest historians of Neo- platonism, Simon and Vacherot, the school of Plotinus was (in defiance of geographical facts) 'the school of Alexandria,' and its inspiration was mainly Egyptian. Vacherot says of Neoplatonism that it is 'essentially and radically oriental, having nothing of Greek thought but its language and procedure.' Few would be found to-day to subscribe to so sweeping a pronouncement; but the existence of an important oriental element in Plotinus' thought is still affirmed by many French and German writers. [p. 129] |
Online Resources | https://uni-koeln.sciebo.de/s/ElUfvVkaaeLIJVk |
{"_index":"sire","_type":"_doc","_id":"554","_score":null,"_source":{"id":554,"authors_free":[{"id":783,"entry_id":554,"agent_type":null,"is_normalised":null,"person_id":65,"institution_id":null,"role":{"id":1,"role_name":"author"},"free_name":"Dodds, Eric R. ","free_first_name":"Eric R. ","free_last_name":"Dodds","norm_person":{"id":65,"first_name":"Eric R. ","last_name":"Dodds","full_name":"Dodds, Eric R. ","short_ident":"","is_classical_name":null,"dnb_url":"http:\/\/d-nb.info\/gnd\/123026288","viaf_url":"","db_url":"","from_claudius":null}}],"entry_title":"The Parmenides of Plato and the Origin of the Neoplatonic 'One' ","main_title":{"title":"The Parmenides of Plato and the Origin of the Neoplatonic 'One' "},"abstract":"THE last phase of Greek philosophy has until recently been less intelli- \r\ngently studied than any other, and in our understanding of its development \r\nthere are still lamentable lacunae. Three errors in particular have in the past \r\nprevented a proper appreciation of Plotinus' place in the history of philosophy. When this false trail was at length abandoned the fashion for orientalizing \r\nexplanations persisted in another guise: to the earliest historians of Neo- \r\nplatonism, Simon and Vacherot, the school of Plotinus was (in defiance of \r\ngeographical facts) 'the school of Alexandria,' and its inspiration was mainly \r\nEgyptian. Vacherot says of Neoplatonism that it is 'essentially and radically \r\noriental, having nothing of Greek thought but its language and procedure.' \r\nFew would be found to-day to subscribe to so sweeping a pronouncement; but \r\nthe existence of an important oriental element in Plotinus' thought is still \r\naffirmed by many French and German writers. [p. 129]","btype":3,"date":"1928","language":"English","online_url":"","online_resources":"https:\/\/uni-koeln.sciebo.de\/s\/ElUfvVkaaeLIJVk","doi_url":null,"categories":[],"authors":[{"id":65,"full_name":"Dodds, Eric R. ","role":{"id":1,"role_name":"author"}}],"book":null,"booksection":null,"article":{"id":554,"journal_id":null,"journal_name":"Classical Quarterly","volume":"22","issue":"3\/4 (Jul. - Oct., 1928),","pages":"129\u2013142"}},"sort":[1928]}
Title | The Homoiomeries of Anaxagoras |
Type | Article |
Language | English |
Date | 1927 |
Journal | The Classical Quarterly |
Volume | 21 |
Issue | 3/4 |
Pages | 133-141 |
Categories | no categories |
Author(s) | Leon, Philip |
Editor(s) | |
Translator(s) |
[Conclusion, p. 141]: Anaxagoras does indeed, as he has been said to do, represent the culminating point of the enquiry into the one bto-tv. That simple enquiry for a simple unity becomes curiously complex, just because of the very simplicity and the thorough-going and uncompromising nature of Anaxagoras' logical mind. It has with him reached a stage where it must become transformed and pass on the one hand into logic in Plato, into the enquiry about the nature of predication through Gorgias and Antisthenes, and on the other hand into metaphysics, the theory of ideas, also in Plato. This central position of Anaxagoras is made clear by the passage discussed, according to which, I think, in considering the 'homoiomeries,' we should look upon parts as 'homoiomerous' primarily to the whole i~c6otov, and only secondarily to subordinate wholes. Indeed, it is implied in Anaxagoras' principle that there are only two entities which are properly wholes, the 0c0/cpo and voDv^. To call anything else a whole is more or less arbitrary, a principle not unworthy of the most thorough-going of modern absolutists. |
Online Resources | https://uni-koeln.sciebo.de/s/FXHNwY19loMmfLj |
{"_index":"sire","_type":"_doc","_id":"733","_score":null,"_source":{"id":733,"authors_free":[{"id":1096,"entry_id":733,"agent_type":null,"is_normalised":null,"person_id":245,"institution_id":null,"role":{"id":1,"role_name":"author"},"free_name":"Leon, Philip","free_first_name":"Philip","free_last_name":"Leon","norm_person":{"id":245,"first_name":"Philip","last_name":"Leon","full_name":"Leon, Philip","short_ident":"","is_classical_name":null,"dnb_url":"","viaf_url":"","db_url":"","from_claudius":null}}],"entry_title":"The Homoiomeries of Anaxagoras","main_title":{"title":"The Homoiomeries of Anaxagoras"},"abstract":"[Conclusion, p. 141]: Anaxagoras does indeed, as he has been said to do, represent the \r\nculminating point of the enquiry into the one bto-tv. That simple enquiry \r\nfor a simple unity becomes curiously complex, just because of the very \r\nsimplicity and the thorough-going and uncompromising nature of Anaxagoras' \r\nlogical mind. It has with him reached a stage where it must become \r\ntransformed and pass on the one hand into logic in Plato, into the enquiry \r\nabout the nature of predication through Gorgias and Antisthenes, and on the \r\nother hand into metaphysics, the theory of ideas, also in Plato. This central \r\nposition of Anaxagoras is made clear by the passage discussed, according \r\nto which, I think, in considering the 'homoiomeries,' we should look upon \r\nparts as 'homoiomerous' primarily to the whole i~c6otov, and only secondarily \r\nto subordinate wholes. Indeed, it is implied in Anaxagoras' principle that \r\nthere are only two entities which are properly wholes, the 0c0\/cpo and voDv^. To call anything else a whole is more or less arbitrary, a principle not \r\nunworthy of the most thorough-going of modern absolutists. ","btype":3,"date":"1927","language":"English","online_url":"","online_resources":"https:\/\/uni-koeln.sciebo.de\/s\/FXHNwY19loMmfLj","doi_url":null,"categories":[],"authors":[{"id":245,"full_name":"Leon, Philip","role":{"id":1,"role_name":"author"}}],"book":null,"booksection":null,"article":{"id":733,"journal_id":null,"journal_name":"The Classical Quarterly","volume":"21","issue":"3\/4","pages":"133-141"}},"sort":[1927]}
Title | Simpl. in Aristot. de Caelo p. 370, 29 ff. H |
Type | Article |
Language | German |
Date | 1924 |
Journal | Hermes |
Volume | 59 |
Issue | 1 |
Pages | 118-119 |
Categories | no categories |
Author(s) | Praechter, Karl |
Editor(s) | |
Translator(s) |
Online Resources | https://uni-koeln.sciebo.de/s/zc8efUUHCZuTFnA |
{"_index":"sire","_type":"_doc","_id":"1477","_score":null,"_source":{"id":1477,"authors_free":[{"id":2558,"entry_id":1477,"agent_type":"person","is_normalised":1,"person_id":293,"institution_id":null,"role":{"id":1,"role_name":"author"},"free_name":"Praechter, Karl","free_first_name":"Karl","free_last_name":"Praechter","norm_person":{"id":293,"first_name":"Karl","last_name":"Praechter","full_name":"Praechter, Karl","short_ident":"","is_classical_name":null,"dnb_url":"http:\/\/d-nb.info\/gnd\/116278609","viaf_url":"","db_url":"","from_claudius":null}}],"entry_title":"Simpl. in Aristot. de Caelo p. 370, 29 ff. H","main_title":{"title":"Simpl. in Aristot. de Caelo p. 370, 29 ff. H"},"abstract":"","btype":3,"date":"1924","language":"German","online_url":"","online_resources":"https:\/\/uni-koeln.sciebo.de\/s\/zc8efUUHCZuTFnA","doi_url":null,"categories":[],"authors":[{"id":293,"full_name":"Praechter, Karl","role":{"id":1,"role_name":"author"}}],"book":null,"booksection":null,"article":{"id":1477,"journal_id":null,"journal_name":"Hermes","volume":"59","issue":"1","pages":"118-119"}},"sort":[1924]}
Title | Nikostratos der Platoniker |
Type | Article |
Language | German |
Date | 1922 |
Journal | Hermes |
Volume | 57 |
Issue | 4 |
Pages | 481-517 |
Categories | no categories |
Author(s) | Praechter, Karl |
Editor(s) | |
Translator(s) |
Als Beitrag zur Vor- und Entwicklungsgeschichte des Neu platonismus auf einem Teilgebiet seiner Lehre möchte [...] die vorliegende Untersuchung betrachtet werden. Ich selbst habe zu zeigen versucht, daß der alexandrinische Neuplatonismus keines wegs die Linie Plotin-Porphyrios-Iamblich fortsetzt, sondern an ein früheres Stadium platonischer Lehrentwicklung anschließt. [pp. 516 f.] |
Online Resources | https://uni-koeln.sciebo.de/s/viSBRYmv6qSxA3q |
{"_index":"sire","_type":"_doc","_id":"775","_score":null,"_source":{"id":775,"authors_free":[{"id":1139,"entry_id":775,"agent_type":null,"is_normalised":null,"person_id":293,"institution_id":null,"role":{"id":1,"role_name":"author"},"free_name":"Praechter, Karl","free_first_name":"Karl","free_last_name":"Praechter","norm_person":{"id":293,"first_name":"Karl","last_name":"Praechter","full_name":"Praechter, Karl","short_ident":"","is_classical_name":null,"dnb_url":"http:\/\/d-nb.info\/gnd\/116278609","viaf_url":"","db_url":"","from_claudius":null}}],"entry_title":"Nikostratos der Platoniker","main_title":{"title":"Nikostratos der Platoniker"},"abstract":"Als Beitrag zur Vor- und Entwicklungsgeschichte des Neu\u00ad\r\nplatonismus auf einem Teilgebiet seiner Lehre m\u00f6chte [...] die \r\nvorliegende Untersuchung betrachtet werden. Ich selbst habe zu \r\nzeigen versucht, da\u00df der alexandrinische Neuplatonismus keines\u00ad\r\nwegs die Linie Plotin-Porphyrios-Iamblich fortsetzt, sondern an ein \r\nfr\u00fcheres Stadium platonischer Lehrentwicklung anschlie\u00dft. [pp. 516 f.]","btype":3,"date":"1922","language":"German","online_url":"","online_resources":"https:\/\/uni-koeln.sciebo.de\/s\/viSBRYmv6qSxA3q","doi_url":null,"categories":[],"authors":[{"id":293,"full_name":"Praechter, Karl","role":{"id":1,"role_name":"author"}}],"book":null,"booksection":null,"article":{"id":775,"journal_id":null,"journal_name":"Hermes","volume":"57","issue":"4","pages":"481-517"}},"sort":[1922]}
Title | Were Aristotle's Intentions in writing the De Anima Forgotten in Late Antiquity? |
Type | Article |
Language | English |
Date | 1997 |
Journal | Documenti e Studi sulla Tradizione Filosofica Medievale |
Volume | 8 |
Pages | 143–157 |
Categories | no categories |
Author(s) | Blumenthal, Henry J. |
Editor(s) | |
Translator(s) |
In general we have to conclude that while the whole "Philoponus” commentary may include a number of explicit references to the biological writings, and while the real Philoponus may often refer to medical and scientific issues, there is no systematic bias towards explaining the contents of the De anima in terms of them. There is, however, just as in the Ps-Simplicius commentary, enough said about such matters, and enough reference made to other parts of the biological corpus, to show that the commentators were still aware of the original intentions of the work — or, at the very least, behaved as if they were — even if they did not always feel bound by them. That awareness was to survive into the Middle Ages as well. [Conclusion, p. 157] |
Online Resources | https://uni-koeln.sciebo.de/s/qhZRe3zhqqbPUeO |
{"_index":"sire","_type":"_doc","_id":"893","_score":null,"_source":{"id":893,"authors_free":[{"id":1316,"entry_id":893,"agent_type":null,"is_normalised":null,"person_id":108,"institution_id":null,"role":{"id":1,"role_name":"author"},"free_name":"Blumenthal, Henry J.","free_first_name":"Henry J.","free_last_name":"Blumenthal","norm_person":{"id":108,"first_name":"Henry J.","last_name":"Blumenthal","full_name":"Blumenthal, Henry J.","short_ident":"","is_classical_name":null,"dnb_url":"http:\/\/d-nb.info\/gnd\/1051543967","viaf_url":"","db_url":"","from_claudius":null}}],"entry_title":"Were Aristotle's Intentions in writing the De Anima Forgotten in Late Antiquity?","main_title":{"title":"Were Aristotle's Intentions in writing the De Anima Forgotten in Late Antiquity?"},"abstract":"In general we have to conclude that while the whole \"Philoponus\u201d commentary may include a number of explicit references to the biological writings, and while the real Philoponus may often refer to medical and scientific issues, there is no systematic bias towards explaining the contents of the De anima in terms of them. There is, however, just as in the Ps-Simplicius commentary, enough said about such matters, and \r\nenough reference made to other parts of the biological corpus, to show that the commentators were still aware of the original intentions of the work \u2014 or, at the very least, behaved as if they were \u2014 even if they did not always feel bound by them. That awareness was to survive into the Middle Ages as well. [Conclusion, p. 157]","btype":3,"date":"1997","language":"English","online_url":"","online_resources":"https:\/\/uni-koeln.sciebo.de\/s\/qhZRe3zhqqbPUeO","doi_url":null,"categories":[],"authors":[{"id":108,"full_name":"Blumenthal, Henry J.","role":{"id":1,"role_name":"author"}}],"book":null,"booksection":null,"article":{"id":893,"journal_id":null,"journal_name":"Documenti e Studi sulla Tradizione Filosofica Medievale","volume":"8","issue":"","pages":"143\u2013157"}},"sort":["Were Aristotle's Intentions in writing the De Anima Forgotten in Late Antiquity?"]}
Title | Were Zeno's Arguments a Reply to Attacks upon Parmenides? |
Type | Article |
Language | English |
Date | 1957 |
Journal | Phronesis |
Volume | 2 |
Issue | 1 |
Pages | 1-9 |
Categories | no categories |
Author(s) | Booth, N.B. |
Editor(s) | |
Translator(s) |
This article by N. B. Booth examines whether Zeno's arguments were a response to criticisms of Parmenides's principle „the One“. Despite evidence that Zeno was concerned with defending Parmenides's „One“, his arguments about plurality seem to refute the "ones" of a plurality. One possible explanation is that Zeno's arguments were used to counter criticisms of Parmenides's „One“ before he produced them. Plato's Parmenides includes a passage in which "Zeno" apologizes for his book on plurality, which has been interpreted as an answer to criticisms of Parmenides's theory, but Booth notes that Plato's characters are idealized and it is not certain that Zeno's arguments were a response to attacks. Booth looks at the arguments themselves for evidence and suggests that if some of Zeno's arguments against plural "ones" were valid against Parmenides's „One“, it would be fair to infer that they were used by hostile critics and Zeno was throwing them back in their faces. [introduction] |
Online Resources | https://uni-koeln.sciebo.de/s/Z24XRGSFJxejYPK |
{"_index":"sire","_type":"_doc","_id":"1127","_score":null,"_source":{"id":1127,"authors_free":[{"id":1702,"entry_id":1127,"agent_type":null,"is_normalised":null,"person_id":10,"institution_id":null,"role":{"id":1,"role_name":"author"},"free_name":"Booth, N.B.","free_first_name":"N.B.","free_last_name":"Booth","norm_person":{"id":10,"first_name":"N. B.","last_name":"Booth","full_name":"Booth, N. B.","short_ident":"","is_classical_name":null,"dnb_url":"","viaf_url":"","db_url":"","from_claudius":null}}],"entry_title":"Were Zeno's Arguments a Reply to Attacks upon Parmenides?","main_title":{"title":"Were Zeno's Arguments a Reply to Attacks upon Parmenides?"},"abstract":"This article by N. B. Booth examines whether Zeno's arguments were a response to criticisms of Parmenides's principle \u201ethe One\u201c. Despite evidence that Zeno was concerned with defending Parmenides's \u201eOne\u201c, his arguments about plurality seem to refute the \"ones\" of a plurality. One possible explanation is that Zeno's arguments were used to counter criticisms of Parmenides's \u201eOne\u201c before he produced them. Plato's Parmenides includes a passage in which \"Zeno\" apologizes for his book on plurality, which has been interpreted as an answer to criticisms of Parmenides's theory, but Booth notes that Plato's characters are idealized and it is not certain that Zeno's arguments were a response to attacks. Booth looks at the arguments themselves for evidence and suggests that if some of Zeno's arguments against plural \"ones\" were valid against Parmenides's \u201eOne\u201c, it would be fair to infer that they were used by hostile critics and Zeno was throwing them back in their faces. [introduction]","btype":3,"date":"1957","language":"English","online_url":"","online_resources":"https:\/\/uni-koeln.sciebo.de\/s\/Z24XRGSFJxejYPK","doi_url":null,"categories":[],"authors":[{"id":10,"full_name":"Booth, N. B.","role":{"id":1,"role_name":"author"}}],"book":null,"booksection":null,"article":{"id":1127,"journal_id":null,"journal_name":"Phronesis","volume":"2","issue":"1","pages":"1-9"}},"sort":["Were Zeno's Arguments a Reply to Attacks upon Parmenides?"]}
Title | What Has Aristotelian Dialectic to Offer a Neoplatonist? A Possible Sample of Iamblichus at Simplicius on the Categories 12,10-13,12 |
Type | Article |
Language | English |
Date | 2012 |
Journal | The International Journal of the Platonic Tradition |
Volume | 6 |
Pages | 173-185 |
Categories | no categories |
Author(s) | Griffin, Michael J. |
Editor(s) | |
Translator(s) |
Simplicius in Cat. 12,10-13,12 presents an interesting justifijication for the study of Aristotle’s Categories, based in Neoplatonic psychology and metaphysics. I suggest that this passage could be regarded as a testimonium to Iamblichus’ reasons for endorsing Porphyry’s selection of the Categories as an introductory text of Platonic philosophy. These Iamblichean arguments, richly grounded in Neoplatonic metaphysics and psychology, may have exercised an influence comparable to Porphyry’s. [authors abstract] |
Online Resources | https://uni-koeln.sciebo.de/s/OkODIHdy69Gu56Q |
{"_index":"sire","_type":"_doc","_id":"937","_score":null,"_source":{"id":937,"authors_free":[{"id":1390,"entry_id":937,"agent_type":null,"is_normalised":null,"person_id":148,"institution_id":null,"role":{"id":1,"role_name":"author"},"free_name":"Griffin, Michael J.","free_first_name":"Michael J.","free_last_name":"Griffin","norm_person":{"id":148,"first_name":"Michael J.","last_name":"Griffin","full_name":"Griffin, Michael J.","short_ident":"","is_classical_name":null,"dnb_url":"http:\/\/d-nb.info\/gnd\/1065676603","viaf_url":"","db_url":"","from_claudius":null}}],"entry_title":"What Has Aristotelian Dialectic to Offer a Neoplatonist? A Possible Sample of Iamblichus at Simplicius on the Categories 12,10-13,12","main_title":{"title":"What Has Aristotelian Dialectic to Offer a Neoplatonist? A Possible Sample of Iamblichus at Simplicius on the Categories 12,10-13,12"},"abstract":"Simplicius in Cat. 12,10-13,12 presents an interesting justif\u0133ication for the study of Aristotle\u2019s Categories, based in Neoplatonic psychology and metaphysics. I suggest that this passage could be regarded as a testimonium to Iamblichus\u2019 reasons for endorsing Porphyry\u2019s selection of the Categories as an introductory text of Platonic philosophy. These Iamblichean arguments, richly grounded in Neoplatonic metaphysics and psychology, may have exercised an influence comparable to Porphyry\u2019s. [authors abstract]","btype":3,"date":"2012","language":"English","online_url":"","online_resources":"https:\/\/uni-koeln.sciebo.de\/s\/OkODIHdy69Gu56Q","doi_url":null,"categories":[],"authors":[{"id":148,"full_name":"Griffin, Michael J.","role":{"id":1,"role_name":"author"}}],"book":null,"booksection":null,"article":{"id":937,"journal_id":null,"journal_name":"The International Journal of the Platonic Tradition","volume":"6","issue":"","pages":"173-185"}},"sort":["What Has Aristotelian Dialectic to Offer a Neoplatonist? A Possible Sample of Iamblichus at Simplicius on the Categories 12,10-13,12"]}
Title | What does Aristotle categorize? Semantics and the early peripatetic reading of the "Categories" |
Type | Article |
Language | English |
Date | 2012 |
Journal | Bulletin of the Institute of Classical Studies |
Volume | 55 |
Issue | 1 |
Pages | 69-108 |
Categories | no categories |
Author(s) | Griffin, Michael J. |
Editor(s) | |
Translator(s) |
One of the more provocative mysteries of later ancient philosophy is how Porphyiy came to situate the Categories of Aristotle at the outset of the nascent Neoplatonic curriculum. After all, the Categories tends to strike modem readers as a temperamentally counter-Platonic work, in which Aristotle grants ontological priority to perceptible subjects over intelligible genera and species, and we are led to wonder how a Platonist would be motivated to encourage its use as a general introduction to philosophy. The commentary tradition has left us with several layers of evidence for Porphyry's reasoning. First, in answer to the general question "Why should a philosopher study the Categories?" we have Porphyry's assertion that the ten Aristotelian schemata of predication carve the genera of being accurately at the joints (in Cat. 58,5-59,33), that this isomorphism between kind of simple referring terms and kinds of beings facilitates human knowledge, and that the philosopher's path therefore begins from the correct inteipretation of the Categories (see for example T9-11, discussed below). Second, in response to the question 'Why is the Categories compatible with Platonism?’, we have Porphyry’s account that the Categories introduces the student to the study of referring terms, which refer primarily to perceptible beings; after we have grasped the correct application of language to perceptibles, however, we are prepared to 'ascend by analogy’ to the study of intelligibles, which is Plato’s ambit. But this pedagogical solution, while it jibes elegantly with Porphyry!s decision to bracket metaphysical questions from introductory logic {cf. Isagoge 4,10-15, with Barnes 2003 ad loc.), also suggests a tension between two layers of Porphyry’s thought about die Categories. On the one hand, we are motivated to read the treatise because its divisions ofmeaningful language exhaustively and accurately picture being; on the other hand, we acknowledge that the text has nothing to say about die most important kind of being, namely intelligible being. In other words, Porphyry’s leading argument in favour of studying the Categories (its comprehensiveness) seems like a strange bedfellow for his leading argument in favour of its compatibility with Platonism (its restrictedness); and the source of this general tension is the first puzzle that I would like to explore in this essay. [Introduction, pp. 69 f.] |
Online Resources | https://uni-koeln.sciebo.de/s/E7XiS12GrRNsPr9 |
{"_index":"sire","_type":"_doc","_id":"1148","_score":null,"_source":{"id":1148,"authors_free":[{"id":1723,"entry_id":1148,"agent_type":null,"is_normalised":null,"person_id":148,"institution_id":null,"role":{"id":1,"role_name":"author"},"free_name":"Griffin, Michael J.","free_first_name":"Michael J.","free_last_name":"Griffin","norm_person":{"id":148,"first_name":"Michael J.","last_name":"Griffin","full_name":"Griffin, Michael J.","short_ident":"","is_classical_name":null,"dnb_url":"http:\/\/d-nb.info\/gnd\/1065676603","viaf_url":"","db_url":"","from_claudius":null}}],"entry_title":"What does Aristotle categorize? Semantics and the early peripatetic reading of the \"Categories\"","main_title":{"title":"What does Aristotle categorize? Semantics and the early peripatetic reading of the \"Categories\""},"abstract":"One of the more provocative mysteries of later ancient philosophy is how Porphyiy came \r\nto situate the Categories of Aristotle at the outset of the nascent Neoplatonic curriculum.\r\nAfter all, the Categories tends to strike modem readers as a temperamentally counter-Platonic work, in which Aristotle grants ontological priority to perceptible subjects over intelligible genera and species, and we are led to wonder how a Platonist would be \r\nmotivated to encourage its use as a general introduction to philosophy. The commentary \r\ntradition has left us with several layers of evidence for Porphyry's reasoning. First, in answer to the general question \"Why should a philosopher study the Categories?\" we have \r\nPorphyry's assertion that the ten Aristotelian schemata of predication carve the genera of \r\nbeing accurately at the joints (in Cat. 58,5-59,33), that this isomorphism between kind of simple referring terms and kinds of beings facilitates human knowledge, and that the \r\nphilosopher's path therefore begins from the correct inteipretation of the Categories (see for example T9-11, discussed below). Second, in response to the question 'Why is the Categories compatible with Platonism?\u2019, we have Porphyry\u2019s account that the Categories introduces the student to the study of referring terms, which refer primarily to perceptible beings; after we have grasped the correct application of language to perceptibles, \r\nhowever, we are prepared to 'ascend by analogy\u2019 to the study of intelligibles, which is \r\nPlato\u2019s ambit. But this pedagogical solution, while it jibes elegantly with Porphyry!s \r\ndecision to bracket metaphysical questions from introductory logic {cf. Isagoge 4,10-15, with Barnes 2003 ad loc.), also suggests a tension between two layers of Porphyry\u2019s thought about die Categories. On the one hand, we are motivated to read the treatise \r\nbecause its divisions ofmeaningful language exhaustively and accurately picture being; on the other hand, we acknowledge that the text has nothing to say about die most important kind of being, namely intelligible being. In other words, Porphyry\u2019s leading \r\nargument in favour of studying the Categories (its comprehensiveness) seems like a strange bedfellow for his leading argument in favour of its compatibility with Platonism \r\n(its restrictedness); and the source of this general tension is the first puzzle that I would like to explore in this essay. [Introduction, pp. 69 f.]","btype":3,"date":"2012","language":"English","online_url":"","online_resources":"https:\/\/uni-koeln.sciebo.de\/s\/E7XiS12GrRNsPr9","doi_url":null,"categories":[],"authors":[{"id":148,"full_name":"Griffin, Michael J.","role":{"id":1,"role_name":"author"}}],"book":null,"booksection":null,"article":{"id":1148,"journal_id":null,"journal_name":"Bulletin of the Institute of Classical Studies","volume":"55","issue":"1","pages":"69-108"}},"sort":["What does Aristotle categorize? Semantics and the early peripatetic reading of the \"Categories\""]}
Title | What goes up: Proclus against Aristotle on the fifth element |
Type | Article |
Language | English |
Date | 2002 |
Journal | Australasian Journal of Philosophy |
Volume | 80 |
Issue | 3 |
Pages | 261-287 |
Categories | no categories |
Author(s) | Baltzly, Dirk |
Editor(s) | |
Translator(s) |
In this paper, I consider Proclus’ arguments against Aristotle on the composition of the heavens from the fifth element, the aether. Proclus argues for the Platonic view (Timaeus 40a) that the heavenly bodies are composed of all four elements, with fire predominating. I think that his discussion exhibits all the methodological features that we find admirable in Aristotle’s largely a priori proto-science. Proclus’ treatment of the question in his commentary on Plato’s Timaeus also provides the fullest statement of a neoplatonic alternative to the Aristotelian theory of the elements. As such, it forms a significant part of a still largely underappreciated neoplatonic legacy to the history of science. [authors abstract] |
Online Resources | https://uni-koeln.sciebo.de/s/M34EGiOeJdMYBkH |
{"_index":"sire","_type":"_doc","_id":"962","_score":null,"_source":{"id":962,"authors_free":[{"id":1444,"entry_id":962,"agent_type":null,"is_normalised":null,"person_id":107,"institution_id":null,"role":{"id":1,"role_name":"author"},"free_name":"Baltzly, Dirk","free_first_name":"Dirk","free_last_name":"Baltzly","norm_person":{"id":107,"first_name":"Dirk","last_name":"Baltzly","full_name":"Baltzly, Dirk","short_ident":"","is_classical_name":null,"dnb_url":"http:\/\/d-nb.info\/gnd\/1150414960","viaf_url":"","db_url":"","from_claudius":null}}],"entry_title":"What goes up: Proclus against Aristotle on the fifth element","main_title":{"title":"What goes up: Proclus against Aristotle on the fifth element"},"abstract":"In this paper, I consider Proclus\u2019 arguments against Aristotle on the composition of the \r\nheavens from the fifth element, the aether. Proclus argues for the Platonic view (Timaeus \r\n40a) that the heavenly bodies are composed of all four elements, with fire predominating. \r\nI think that his discussion exhibits all the methodological features that we find admirable \r\nin Aristotle\u2019s largely a priori proto-science. Proclus\u2019 treatment of the question in his \r\ncommentary on Plato\u2019s Timaeus also provides the fullest statement of a neoplatonic \r\nalternative to the Aristotelian theory of the elements. As such, it forms a significant part of \r\na still largely underappreciated neoplatonic legacy to the history of science. [authors abstract]","btype":3,"date":"2002","language":"English","online_url":"","online_resources":"https:\/\/uni-koeln.sciebo.de\/s\/M34EGiOeJdMYBkH","doi_url":null,"categories":[],"authors":[{"id":107,"full_name":"Baltzly, Dirk","role":{"id":1,"role_name":"author"}}],"book":null,"booksection":null,"article":{"id":962,"journal_id":null,"journal_name":"Australasian Journal of Philosophy","volume":"80","issue":"3","pages":"261-287"}},"sort":["What goes up: Proclus against Aristotle on the fifth element"]}
Title | What is Platonism? |
Type | Article |
Language | English |
Date | 2005 |
Journal | Journal of the History of Philosophy |
Volume | 43 |
Issue | 3 |
Pages | 253-276 |
Categories | no categories |
Author(s) | Gerson, Lloyd P. |
Editor(s) | |
Translator(s) |
My main conclusion is that we should understand Platonism historically as consisting in fidelity to the principles of “top-downism.” So understanding it, we havea relatively sharp critical tool for deciding who was and who was not a Platonist despite their silence or protestations to the contrary. Unquestionably, the most important figure in this regard is Aristotle. I would not like to end this historical inquiry, however, without suggesting a philosophical moral. The moral is that there are at least some reasons for claiming that a truly anti-Platonic Aristotelianism is not philosophically in the cards, so to speak. Thus, if one rigorously and honestly seeks to remove the principles of Platonism from a putatively Aristotelian position, what would remain would be incoherent and probably indefensible. Thus, an Aristotelian ontology of the sensible world that excluded the ontological priority of the supersensible is probably unsustainable. And an Aristotelian psychology that did not recognize the priority and irreducibility of intellect to soul would be similarly beyond repair.89 What contemporary exponents of versions of Platonism or Aristotelianism should perhaps conclude from a study of the history is that, rather than standing in opposition to each other, merger, or at least synergy, ought to be the order of the day.[conclusion, p. 276] |
Online Resources | https://uni-koeln.sciebo.de/s/Goxyyq1Id3kdZDT |
{"_index":"sire","_type":"_doc","_id":"1317","_score":null,"_source":{"id":1317,"authors_free":[{"id":1951,"entry_id":1317,"agent_type":"person","is_normalised":1,"person_id":46,"institution_id":null,"role":{"id":1,"role_name":"author"},"free_name":"Gerson, Lloyd P.","free_first_name":"Lloyd P.","free_last_name":"Gerson","norm_person":{"id":46,"first_name":"Lloyd P.","last_name":"Gerson","full_name":"Gerson, Lloyd P.","short_ident":"","is_classical_name":null,"dnb_url":"http:\/\/d-nb.info\/gnd\/131525573","viaf_url":"","db_url":"","from_claudius":null}}],"entry_title":"What is Platonism?","main_title":{"title":"What is Platonism?"},"abstract":"My main conclusion is that we should understand Platonism historically as consisting in fidelity to the principles of \u201ctop-downism.\u201d So understanding it, we havea relatively sharp critical tool for deciding who was and who was not a Platonist despite their silence or protestations to the contrary. Unquestionably, the most important figure in this regard is Aristotle. I would not like to end this historical inquiry, however, without suggesting a philosophical moral. The moral is that there\r\nare at least some reasons for claiming that a truly anti-Platonic Aristotelianism is not philosophically in the cards, so to speak. Thus, if one rigorously and honestly seeks to remove the principles of Platonism from a putatively Aristotelian position, what would remain would be incoherent and probably indefensible. Thus, an Aristotelian ontology of the sensible world that excluded the ontological priority of the supersensible is probably unsustainable. And an Aristotelian psychology that did not recognize the priority and irreducibility of intellect to soul would be\r\nsimilarly beyond repair.89 What contemporary exponents of versions of Platonism or Aristotelianism should perhaps conclude from a study of the history is that, rather than standing in opposition to each other, merger, or at least synergy, ought to be the order of the day.[conclusion, p. 276]","btype":3,"date":"2005","language":"English","online_url":"","online_resources":"https:\/\/uni-koeln.sciebo.de\/s\/Goxyyq1Id3kdZDT","doi_url":null,"categories":[],"authors":[{"id":46,"full_name":"Gerson, Lloyd P.","role":{"id":1,"role_name":"author"}}],"book":null,"booksection":null,"article":{"id":1317,"journal_id":null,"journal_name":"Journal of the History of Philosophy","volume":"43","issue":"3","pages":"253-276"}},"sort":["What is Platonism?"]}
Title | Where to Live the Philosophical Life in the Sixth Century? Damascius, Simplicius, and the Return from Persia |
Type | Article |
Language | English |
Date | 2005 |
Journal | Greek, Roman, and Byzantine Studies |
Volume | 45 |
Issue | 3 |
Pages | 285-315 |
Categories | no categories |
Author(s) | Watts, Edward Jay |
Editor(s) | |
Translator(s) |
The closing of the Neoplatonic school in Athens by Justinian in 532 was not the end of classical philosophy, for when they returned to the Empire from Persia two years later the philosophers did not need to reconstitute the school at Harran or at any particular city in order to continue their philosophical activities. [author's abstract] |
Online Resources | https://uni-koeln.sciebo.de/s/qb6W6lKeoD2R4gl |
{"_index":"sire","_type":"_doc","_id":"441","_score":null,"_source":{"id":441,"authors_free":[{"id":593,"entry_id":441,"agent_type":null,"is_normalised":null,"person_id":357,"institution_id":null,"role":{"id":1,"role_name":"author"},"free_name":"Watts, Edward Jay","free_first_name":"Edward Jay","free_last_name":"Watts","norm_person":{"id":357,"first_name":"Edward Jay","last_name":"Watts","full_name":"Watts, Edward Jay","short_ident":"","is_classical_name":null,"dnb_url":"http:\/\/d-nb.info\/gnd\/131826530","viaf_url":"","db_url":"","from_claudius":null}}],"entry_title":"Where to Live the Philosophical Life in the Sixth Century? Damascius, Simplicius, and the Return from Persia","main_title":{"title":"Where to Live the Philosophical Life in the Sixth Century? Damascius, Simplicius, and the Return from Persia"},"abstract":"The closing of the Neoplatonic school in Athens by Justinian in 532 was not the end of classical philosophy, for when they returned to the Empire from Persia two years later the philosophers did not need to reconstitute the school at Harran or at any particular city in order to continue their philosophical activities. [author's abstract]","btype":3,"date":"2005","language":"English","online_url":"","online_resources":"https:\/\/uni-koeln.sciebo.de\/s\/qb6W6lKeoD2R4gl","doi_url":null,"categories":[],"authors":[{"id":357,"full_name":"Watts, Edward Jay","role":{"id":1,"role_name":"author"}}],"book":null,"booksection":null,"article":{"id":441,"journal_id":null,"journal_name":"Greek, Roman, and Byzantine Studies","volume":"45","issue":"3","pages":"285-315"}},"sort":["Where to Live the Philosophical Life in the Sixth Century? Damascius, Simplicius, and the Return from Persia"]}
Title | Where was Simplicius? |
Type | Article |
Language | English |
Date | 1992 |
Journal | The Journal of Hellenic Studies |
Volume | 112 |
Pages | 143 |
Categories | no categories |
Author(s) | Foulkes, Paul |
Editor(s) | |
Translator(s) |
In Simplicius: sa vie, son oeuvre, sa survie (Berlin 1987, reviewed in JHS cx [1990] 244-45), the editor, Mme I. Hadot, in the first part of the biographical introduction, cites Agathias Hist. ii 31, 4. This is usually taken to show that the Neoplatonists, who had fled to the Persian court when Justinian closed down the Academy in 529, went back to Athens after 532. That view, she holds, rests on a misreading of the text (…δεῖν ἐκείνους τοὺς ἄνδρας ἐς τὰ σφέτερα ἤθη κατιόντας βιοτεύειν ἀδεῶς τὸ λοιπὸν ὲφ᾿ ἐαυτ–οῖσ…). However, she herself misconstrues ἐφ᾿ ἑαυτ–οῖς as ‘selon leur choix’': that is, on returning from exile to their own accustomed places, these men should henceforth live without fear as they might choose. To yield that version, the Greek would have to be καθ᾿ ἑαυτοὺς. The actual expression means ‘amongst themselves’: they might philosophise, but not in public. That a touch of private heterodoxy amongst the learned few is harmless if it does not stir up the ignorant many was well understood, indeed explicitly so later, in Islam and mediaeval Christianity. |
Online Resources | https://uni-koeln.sciebo.de/s/8tpRlB0YO8USEBq |
{"_index":"sire","_type":"_doc","_id":"901","_score":null,"_source":{"id":901,"authors_free":[{"id":1330,"entry_id":901,"agent_type":null,"is_normalised":null,"person_id":121,"institution_id":null,"role":{"id":1,"role_name":"author"},"free_name":"Foulkes, Paul","free_first_name":"Paul","free_last_name":"Foulkes","norm_person":{"id":121,"first_name":"Paul","last_name":"Foulkes","full_name":"Foulkes, Paul","short_ident":"","is_classical_name":null,"dnb_url":"http:\/\/d-nb.info\/gnd\/127222294","viaf_url":"","db_url":"","from_claudius":null}}],"entry_title":"Where was Simplicius?","main_title":{"title":"Where was Simplicius?"},"abstract":"In Simplicius: sa vie, son oeuvre, sa survie (Berlin 1987, reviewed in JHS cx [1990] 244-45), the editor, Mme I. Hadot, in the first part of the biographical introduction, cites Agathias Hist. ii 31, 4. This is usually taken to show that the Neoplatonists, who had fled to the Persian court when Justinian closed down the Academy in 529, went back to Athens after 532. That view, she holds, rests on a misreading of the text (\u2026\u03b4\u03b5\u1fd6\u03bd \u1f10\u03ba\u03b5\u03af\u03bd\u03bf\u03c5\u03c2 \u03c4\u03bf\u1f7a\u03c2 \u1f04\u03bd\u03b4\u03c1\u03b1\u03c2 \u1f10\u03c2 \u03c4\u1f70 \u03c3\u03c6\u03ad\u03c4\u03b5\u03c1\u03b1 \u1f24\u03b8\u03b7 \u03ba\u03b1\u03c4\u03b9\u03cc\u03bd\u03c4\u03b1\u03c2 \u03b2\u03b9\u03bf\u03c4\u03b5\u03cd\u03b5\u03b9\u03bd \u1f00\u03b4\u03b5\u1ff6\u03c2 \u03c4\u1f78 \u03bb\u03bf\u03b9\u03c0\u1f78\u03bd \u1f72\u03c6\u1fbf \u1f10\u03b1\u03c5\u03c4\u2013\u03bf\u1fd6\u03c3\u2026). However, she herself misconstrues \u1f10\u03c6\u1fbf \u1f11\u03b1\u03c5\u03c4\u2013\u03bf\u1fd6\u03c2 as \u2018selon leur choix\u2019': that is, on returning from exile to their own accustomed places, these men should henceforth live without fear as they might choose. To yield that version, the Greek would have to be \u03ba\u03b1\u03b8\u1fbf \u1f11\u03b1\u03c5\u03c4\u03bf\u1f7a\u03c2. The actual expression means \u2018amongst themselves\u2019: they might philosophise, but not in public. That a touch of private heterodoxy amongst the learned few is harmless if it does not stir up the ignorant many was well understood, indeed explicitly so later, in Islam and mediaeval Christianity.","btype":3,"date":"1992","language":"English","online_url":"","online_resources":"https:\/\/uni-koeln.sciebo.de\/s\/8tpRlB0YO8USEBq","doi_url":null,"categories":[],"authors":[{"id":121,"full_name":"Foulkes, Paul","role":{"id":1,"role_name":"author"}}],"book":null,"booksection":null,"article":{"id":901,"journal_id":null,"journal_name":"The Journal of Hellenic Studies","volume":"112","issue":"","pages":"143"}},"sort":["Where was Simplicius?"]}
Title | Which ‘Athenodorus’ commented on Aristotle's "Categories"? |
Type | Article |
Language | English |
Date | 2013 |
Journal | The Classical Quarterly |
Volume | 63 |
Issue | 1 |
Pages | 199-208 |
Categories | no categories |
Author(s) | Griffin, Michael J. |
Editor(s) | |
Translator(s) |
In this note I would like to revisit the identity of one of the Categories’earliest critics, a Stoic identified only as ‘Athenodorus’in the pages of Dexippus, Porphyry and Simplicius. There is a strong consensus identifying this ‘Athenodorus’with Athenodorus Calvus, a tutor of Octavian and correspondent of Cicero, roughly contem- porary with Andronicus of Rhodes.5 I want to suggest several reasons for reconsidering this identification. In particular, I want to argue that a certain Athenodorus mentioned by Diogenes Laertius (7.68) is on philosophical grounds a compelling candidate for identi- fication with the critic of the Categories, and that Diogenes’Athenodorus is relatively unlikely to be Calvus. As an alternative to Calvus, I tentatively advance the possibility that our Athenodorus may belong to a generation of Stoic philosophers who conducted work on the Categories in the Hellenistic period, prior to the activity of Andronicus in the first century, and under the title Before the Topics (see Simpl. in Cat. 379.9, who observes that Andronicus of Rhodes was aware of this title and rejected it). [p. 200] |
Online Resources | https://uni-koeln.sciebo.de/s/KQ20eDoKvhJNwR4 |
{"_index":"sire","_type":"_doc","_id":"821","_score":null,"_source":{"id":821,"authors_free":[{"id":1222,"entry_id":821,"agent_type":null,"is_normalised":null,"person_id":148,"institution_id":null,"role":{"id":1,"role_name":"author"},"free_name":"Griffin, Michael J.","free_first_name":"Michael J.","free_last_name":"Griffin","norm_person":{"id":148,"first_name":"Michael J.","last_name":"Griffin","full_name":"Griffin, Michael J.","short_ident":"","is_classical_name":null,"dnb_url":"http:\/\/d-nb.info\/gnd\/1065676603","viaf_url":"","db_url":"","from_claudius":null}}],"entry_title":"Which \u2018Athenodorus\u2019 commented on Aristotle's \"Categories\"?","main_title":{"title":"Which \u2018Athenodorus\u2019 commented on Aristotle's \"Categories\"?"},"abstract":"In this note I would like to revisit the identity of one of the Categories\u2019earliest\r\ncritics, a Stoic identified only as \u2018Athenodorus\u2019in the pages of Dexippus, Porphyry\r\nand Simplicius. There is a strong consensus identifying this \u2018Athenodorus\u2019with\r\nAthenodorus Calvus, a tutor of Octavian and correspondent of Cicero, roughly contem-\r\nporary with Andronicus of Rhodes.5 I want to suggest several reasons for reconsidering\r\nthis identification. In particular, I want to argue that a certain Athenodorus mentioned by\r\nDiogenes Laertius (7.68) is on philosophical grounds a compelling candidate for identi-\r\nfication with the critic of the Categories, and that Diogenes\u2019Athenodorus is relatively\r\nunlikely to be Calvus. As an alternative to Calvus, I tentatively advance the possibility\r\nthat our Athenodorus may belong to a generation of Stoic philosophers who conducted\r\nwork on the Categories in the Hellenistic period, prior to the activity of Andronicus in\r\nthe first century, and under the title Before the Topics (see Simpl. in Cat. 379.9, who\r\nobserves that Andronicus of Rhodes was aware of this title and rejected it). [p. 200]","btype":3,"date":"2013","language":"English","online_url":"","online_resources":"https:\/\/uni-koeln.sciebo.de\/s\/KQ20eDoKvhJNwR4","doi_url":null,"categories":[],"authors":[{"id":148,"full_name":"Griffin, Michael J.","role":{"id":1,"role_name":"author"}}],"book":null,"booksection":null,"article":{"id":821,"journal_id":null,"journal_name":"The Classical Quarterly","volume":"63","issue":"1","pages":"199-208"}},"sort":["Which \u2018Athenodorus\u2019 commented on Aristotle's \"Categories\"?"]}
Title | Why Does Plato's Element Theory Conflict With Mathematics (Arist. Cael. 299a2-6)? |
Type | Article |
Language | English |
Date | 2003 |
Journal | Rheinisches Museum für Philologie |
Volume | 146 |
Issue | 3/4 |
Pages | 328-345 |
Categories | no categories |
Author(s) | Kouremenos, Theokritos |
Editor(s) | |
Translator(s) |
In Cael. 3.1 Aristotle argues against those who posit that all bodies are generated because they are made from, and dissolve into, planes, namely Plato and perhaps other members of the Academy who subscribed to the Timaeus physics (cf. Simplicius, In Cael. 561,8-11 [Heiberg]). ]). In his Timaeus Plato assigns to each of the traditional Empedoclean elements a regular polyhedron: the tetra- hedron or pyramid to fire, the cube to earth, the octahedron to air and the icosahedron to water... [p. 328] |
Online Resources | https://uni-koeln.sciebo.de/s/xotNGBOXS7M4jeg |
{"_index":"sire","_type":"_doc","_id":"984","_score":null,"_source":{"id":984,"authors_free":[{"id":1485,"entry_id":984,"agent_type":null,"is_normalised":null,"person_id":219,"institution_id":null,"role":{"id":1,"role_name":"author"},"free_name":"Kouremenos, Theokritos","free_first_name":"Theokritos","free_last_name":"Kouremenos","norm_person":{"id":219,"first_name":"Theokritos","last_name":"Kouremenos","full_name":"Kouremenos, Theokritos","short_ident":"","is_classical_name":null,"dnb_url":"http:\/\/d-nb.info\/gnd\/113872224","viaf_url":"","db_url":"","from_claudius":null}}],"entry_title":"Why Does Plato's Element Theory Conflict With Mathematics (Arist. Cael. 299a2-6)?","main_title":{"title":"Why Does Plato's Element Theory Conflict With Mathematics (Arist. Cael. 299a2-6)?"},"abstract":"In Cael. 3.1 Aristotle argues against those who posit that all bodies are generated because they are made from, and dissolve into, \r\nplanes, namely Plato and perhaps other members of the Academy who subscribed to the Timaeus physics (cf. Simplicius, In Cael. \r\n561,8-11 [Heiberg]). ]). In his Timaeus Plato assigns to each of the \r\ntraditional Empedoclean elements a regular polyhedron: the tetra- hedron or pyramid to fire, the cube to earth, the octahedron to air and the icosahedron to water... [p. 328]","btype":3,"date":"2003","language":"English","online_url":"","online_resources":"https:\/\/uni-koeln.sciebo.de\/s\/xotNGBOXS7M4jeg","doi_url":null,"categories":[],"authors":[{"id":219,"full_name":"Kouremenos, Theokritos","role":{"id":1,"role_name":"author"}}],"book":null,"booksection":null,"article":{"id":984,"journal_id":null,"journal_name":"Rheinisches Museum f\u00fcr Philologie","volume":"146","issue":"3\/4","pages":"328-345"}},"sort":["Why Does Plato's Element Theory Conflict With Mathematics (Arist. Cael. 299a2-6)?"]}