ΠΕΡΙ ΦΥΣΕΩΣ: Zur Frühgeschichte der Buchtitel, 1970
By: Schmalzriedt, Egidius
Title ΠΕΡΙ ΦΥΣΕΩΣ: Zur Frühgeschichte der Buchtitel
Type Monograph
Language German
Date 1970
Publication Place München
Publisher Fink
Categories no categories
Author(s) Schmalzriedt, Egidius
Editor(s)
Translator(s)

{"_index":"sire","_type":"_doc","_id":"58","_score":null,"_source":{"id":58,"authors_free":[{"id":66,"entry_id":58,"agent_type":null,"is_normalised":null,"person_id":534,"institution_id":null,"role":{"id":1,"role_name":"author"},"free_name":"Schmalzriedt, Egidius","free_first_name":"Egidius","free_last_name":"Schmalzriedt","norm_person":{"id":534,"first_name":"Egidius","last_name":"Schmalzriedt","full_name":"Schmalzriedt, Egidius","short_ident":"","is_classical_name":null,"dnb_url":"http:\/\/d-nb.info\/gnd\/123026261","viaf_url":"","db_url":"","from_claudius":null}}],"entry_title":"\u03a0\u0395\u03a1\u0399 \u03a6\u03a5\u03a3\u0395\u03a9\u03a3: Zur Fr\u00fchgeschichte der Buchtitel","main_title":{"title":"\u03a0\u0395\u03a1\u0399 \u03a6\u03a5\u03a3\u0395\u03a9\u03a3: Zur Fr\u00fchgeschichte der Buchtitel"},"abstract":"","btype":1,"date":"1970","language":"German","online_url":"","online_resources":"https:\/\/uni-koeln.sciebo.de\/s\/jDt8nqgkEW6wFPO","doi_url":null,"categories":[],"authors":[{"id":534,"full_name":"Schmalzriedt, Egidius","role":{"id":1,"role_name":"author"}}],"book":{"id":58,"pubplace":"M\u00fcnchen","publisher":"Fink","series":"","volume":"","edition_no":null,"valid_from":null,"valid_until":null},"booksection":null,"article":null},"sort":[1970]}

The Renaissance discovery of classical antiquity, 1969
By: Weiss, Roberto
Title The Renaissance discovery of classical antiquity
Type Monograph
Language English
Date 1969
Publication Place Oxford – New York
Publisher Blackwell
Categories no categories
Author(s) Weiss, Roberto
Editor(s)
Translator(s)
The author traces the rise of a new attitude to classical antiquity, an attitude which became noticeable in the late 13th century but which came fully of age in the first half of the 15th century with humanists such as Poggio and Flavio Biodon. The book covers the period 1300 to 1527. [offical abstract]

{"_index":"sire","_type":"_doc","_id":"191","_score":null,"_source":{"id":191,"authors_free":[{"id":247,"entry_id":191,"agent_type":null,"is_normalised":null,"person_id":533,"institution_id":null,"role":{"id":1,"role_name":"author"},"free_name":"Weiss, Roberto","free_first_name":"Roberto","free_last_name":"Weiss","norm_person":{"id":533,"first_name":"Roberto","last_name":"Weiss","full_name":"Weiss, Roberto","short_ident":"","is_classical_name":null,"dnb_url":"http:\/\/d-nb.info\/gnd\/129054968","viaf_url":"","db_url":"","from_claudius":null}}],"entry_title":"The Renaissance discovery of classical antiquity","main_title":{"title":"The Renaissance discovery of classical antiquity"},"abstract":"The author traces the rise of a new attitude to classical antiquity, an attitude which became noticeable in the late 13th century but which came fully of age in the first half of the 15th century with humanists such as Poggio and Flavio Biodon. The book covers the period 1300 to 1527. [offical abstract]","btype":1,"date":"1969","language":"English","online_url":"","online_resources":"https:\/\/uni-koeln.sciebo.de\/s\/hWocUhaP31pptJ7","doi_url":null,"categories":[],"authors":[{"id":533,"full_name":"Weiss, Roberto","role":{"id":1,"role_name":"author"}}],"book":{"id":191,"pubplace":"Oxford \u2013 \tNew York","publisher":"Blackwell","series":"","volume":"","edition_no":null,"valid_from":null,"valid_until":null},"booksection":null,"article":null},"sort":[1969]}

Das Corollarium de Tempore des Simplikios und die Aporien des Aristoteles zur Zeit, 1969
By: Meyer, Hubert 
Title Das Corollarium de Tempore des Simplikios und die Aporien des Aristoteles zur Zeit
Type Monograph
Language German
Date 1969
Publication Place Meisenheim am Glan
Publisher Anton Hain
Series Monographien zur Naturphilosophie
Volume 8
Categories no categories
Author(s) Meyer, Hubert 
Editor(s)
Translator(s)
Review: In recent years, there has been a renewed interest in the period of Greek philosophy after Aristotle. Since ancient Greek thought exhibits unbroken continuity, the commentaries on Aristotle from late antiquity retain an authenticity and value for the study of Aristotle himself, which have not always been sufficiently recognized. This extensive and learned work is a study of time as presented by Simplicius in his commentary on Aristotle's Physics and in the Doubts and Solutions of Simplicius' teacher, Damascius. It sheds new light not only on the Neoplatonic philosophy of time but also on the notorious "difficulties" of Aristotle regarding time. The work presents a significant amount of philosophical argument, often complex and subtle. Therefore, some oversimplification is necessary. Damascius and Simplicius utilize materials from two different philosophies of time: Aristotle's and Plotinus'. Aristotle's view is that time is the number of motion according to before and after, based on the phenomenon of regular and endless physical motion. Although number, in Aristotle, is a mathematical abstraction, time, being a number, is not merely ideal or mathematical but is actually verified in the physical world. Soul or mind is needed to make the before-and-after of physical motion actually numbered. The "matter" of time, the endless motion of nature (especially the heavens), is real, not merely ideal or mathematical. The form of time is determined by the real relation of before and after, making time a real category, one of the modes of being. Time is the way of being whose being consists in becoming. The other philosophy of time influencing Damascius and Simplicius is the more "idealist" Neoplatonic one, which bases time on the soul. According to Plotinus, the number of motion is an applied number. Eternity is the life of mind (nous), and time is the life of the world-soul. Numbers exist in the realm of mind or being or ideal forms, the second hypostasis of Plotinus. When mind descends into body, constituting soul or the third hypostasis, the life of mind or eternity becomes an activity of soul or time. Time is a psychic measuring, corresponding to Augustine's definition of time as a disrensio animae. Simplicius, like other ancient and medieval commentators, aims not only at a scholarly reconstruction of Aristotle's "difficulties" but at a real solution to the philosophical problem of time. The commentator's new and original philosophy emerges during the exposition of Aristotle's text. Simplicius' thesis is that the reality of time is the present moment, or now, or point of time, which is endlessly repeated. However, this cannot be a correct commentary on Aristotle, for whom time is solidly based on real physical motion. Simplicius' view of time is more abstract since he overlooks the reality of motion. The central part of Meyer's book examines in detail the philosophy of time in the Greek text of the Corollarium. Simplicius' view is that time is in becoming, not in being or eternity. Time's being is in becoming, and the only being in becoming is the "now," which makes time the "now." Simplicius contrasts this with his more Platonic teacher, Damascius, for whom eternity, to aei, or the realm of being, contains a form of time, a supra-temporal whole-time, or time-number, or mathematical "time," the unenfolded structure of number, which, in turn, contains time or continual becoming. Simplicius replies in a more Aristotelian fashion, arguing that Damascius' region of the "always" or "ever" of time, or time as a whole, is entirely unnecessary. Time flows infinitely, an always-becoming, but this infinity of time is not an actual whole. Time flows into infinity, but there is no actual infinite or eternal whole, as personified by Damascius' Demiourgos. Simplicius' interpretation is part of the wider movement of thought in later antiquity when time as the number of motion is forgotten and replaced by a more abstract definition. The interest in these thinkers, Damascius and Simplicius, lies in their providing us with variants or subspecies of the two great masters, Plato and Aristotle. Meyer's learned work makes these obscure texts widely accessible, and his interpretations of the rich material are cautious and sound. The presentation is not [iir die Menge; and, it is sometimes not very clear just what Greek distinctions are being noted by certain G e r m a n distinctions. There are misprints in French, G e r m a n, and Greek. The work is a fine contribution to scholarship. PAUL J. W. MILLER

{"_index":"sire","_type":"_doc","_id":"66","_score":null,"_source":{"id":66,"authors_free":[{"id":74,"entry_id":66,"agent_type":null,"is_normalised":null,"person_id":441,"institution_id":null,"role":{"id":1,"role_name":"author"},"free_name":"Meyer, Hubert\u00a0","free_first_name":"Hubert","free_last_name":"Meyer","norm_person":{"id":441,"first_name":"Hubert","last_name":"Meyer","full_name":"Meyer, Hubert\u00a0","short_ident":"","is_classical_name":null,"dnb_url":"","viaf_url":"","db_url":"","from_claudius":null}}],"entry_title":"Das Corollarium de Tempore des Simplikios und die Aporien des Aristoteles zur Zeit","main_title":{"title":"Das Corollarium de Tempore des Simplikios und die Aporien des Aristoteles zur Zeit"},"abstract":"Review: In recent years, there has been a renewed interest in the period of Greek philosophy after Aristotle. Since ancient Greek thought exhibits unbroken continuity, the commentaries on Aristotle from late antiquity retain an authenticity and value for the study of Aristotle himself, which have not always been sufficiently recognized. This extensive and learned work is a study of time as presented by Simplicius in his commentary on Aristotle's Physics and in the Doubts and Solutions of Simplicius' teacher, Damascius. It sheds new light not only on the Neoplatonic philosophy of time but also on the notorious \"difficulties\" of Aristotle regarding time.\r\nThe work presents a significant amount of philosophical argument, often complex and subtle. Therefore, some oversimplification is necessary. Damascius and Simplicius utilize materials from two different philosophies of time: Aristotle's and Plotinus'. Aristotle's view is that time is the number of motion according to before and after, based on the phenomenon of regular and endless physical motion. Although number, in Aristotle, is a mathematical abstraction, time, being a number, is not merely ideal or mathematical but is actually verified in the physical world. Soul or mind is needed to make the before-and-after of physical motion actually numbered. The \"matter\" of time, the endless motion of nature (especially the heavens), is real, not merely ideal or mathematical. The form of time is determined by the real relation of before and after, making time a real category, one of the modes of being. Time is the way of being whose being consists in becoming.\r\nThe other philosophy of time influencing Damascius and Simplicius is the more \"idealist\" Neoplatonic one, which bases time on the soul. According to Plotinus, the number of motion is an applied number. Eternity is the life of mind (nous), and time is the life of the world-soul. Numbers exist in the realm of mind or being or ideal forms, the second hypostasis of Plotinus. When mind descends into body, constituting soul or the third hypostasis, the life of mind or eternity becomes an activity of soul or time. Time is a psychic measuring, corresponding to Augustine's definition of time as a disrensio animae.\r\nSimplicius, like other ancient and medieval commentators, aims not only at a scholarly reconstruction of Aristotle's \"difficulties\" but at a real solution to the philosophical problem of time. The commentator's new and original philosophy emerges during the exposition of Aristotle's text. Simplicius' thesis is that the reality of time is the present moment, or now, or point of time, which is endlessly repeated. However, this cannot be a correct commentary on Aristotle, for whom time is solidly based on real physical motion. Simplicius' view of time is more abstract since he overlooks the reality of motion.\r\nThe central part of Meyer's book examines in detail the philosophy of time in the Greek text of the Corollarium. Simplicius' view is that time is in becoming, not in being or eternity. Time's being is in becoming, and the only being in becoming is the \"now,\" which makes time the \"now.\" Simplicius contrasts this with his more Platonic teacher, Damascius, for whom eternity, to aei, or the realm of being, contains a form of time, a supra-temporal whole-time, or time-number, or mathematical \"time,\" the unenfolded structure of number, which, in turn, contains time or continual becoming.\r\nSimplicius replies in a more Aristotelian fashion, arguing that Damascius' region of the \"always\" or \"ever\" of time, or time as a whole, is entirely unnecessary. Time flows infinitely, an always-becoming, but this infinity of time is not an actual whole. Time flows into infinity, but there is no actual infinite or eternal whole, as personified by Damascius' Demiourgos.\r\nSimplicius' interpretation is part of the wider movement of thought in later antiquity when time as the number of motion is forgotten and replaced by a more abstract definition.\r\nThe interest in these thinkers, Damascius and Simplicius, lies in their providing us with variants or subspecies of the two great masters, Plato and Aristotle. Meyer's learned work makes these obscure texts widely accessible, and his interpretations of the rich material are cautious and sound. The presentation is not [iir die Menge; and, it is sometimes not very clear just what Greek distinctions are being noted by certain G e r m a n distinctions. There are misprints in French, G e r m a n, and Greek. The work is a fine contribution to scholarship.\r\nPAUL J. W. MILLER\r\n","btype":1,"date":"1969","language":"German","online_url":"","online_resources":"https:\/\/uni-koeln.sciebo.de\/s\/f9MAopVd91xU5pu","doi_url":null,"categories":[],"authors":[{"id":441,"full_name":"Meyer, Hubert\u00a0","role":{"id":1,"role_name":"author"}}],"book":{"id":66,"pubplace":"Meisenheim am Glan","publisher":"Anton Hain","series":"Monographien zur Naturphilosophie","volume":"8","edition_no":"","valid_from":null,"valid_until":null},"booksection":null,"article":null},"sort":[1969]}

Aristote, Du ciel. Texte établi et traduit par Paul Moraux, 1965
By: Moraux, Paul, Aristote
Title Aristote, Du ciel. Texte établi et traduit par Paul Moraux
Type Monograph
Language French
Date 1965
Publication Place Paris
Publisher Les Belles Lettres
Categories no categories
Author(s) Moraux, Paul , Aristote
Editor(s)
Translator(s)

{"_index":"sire","_type":"_doc","_id":"1374","_score":null,"_source":{"id":1374,"authors_free":[{"id":2084,"entry_id":1374,"agent_type":"person","is_normalised":1,"person_id":137,"institution_id":null,"role":{"id":1,"role_name":"author"},"free_name":"Moraux, Paul","free_first_name":"Paul","free_last_name":"Moraux","norm_person":{"id":137,"first_name":"Paul ","last_name":"Moraux","full_name":"Moraux, Paul ","short_ident":"","is_classical_name":null,"dnb_url":"http:\/\/d-nb.info\/gnd\/117755591","viaf_url":"","db_url":"","from_claudius":null}},{"id":2113,"entry_id":1374,"agent_type":"person","is_normalised":null,"person_id":263,"institution_id":null,"role":{"id":1,"role_name":"author"},"free_name":"Aristote","free_first_name":"","free_last_name":"","norm_person":{"id":263,"first_name":"","last_name":"","full_name":"Aristoteles","short_ident":"","is_classical_name":null,"dnb_url":"http:\/\/d-nb.info\/gnd\/118650130","viaf_url":"","db_url":"","from_claudius":null}}],"entry_title":"Aristote, Du ciel. Texte \u00e9tabli et traduit par Paul Moraux","main_title":{"title":"Aristote, Du ciel. Texte \u00e9tabli et traduit par Paul Moraux"},"abstract":"","btype":1,"date":"1965","language":"French","online_url":"","online_resources":"https:\/\/uni-koeln.sciebo.de\/s\/W0FrLs9BKUEyoH3","doi_url":null,"categories":[],"authors":[{"id":137,"full_name":"Moraux, Paul ","role":{"id":1,"role_name":"author"}},{"id":263,"full_name":"Aristoteles","role":{"id":1,"role_name":"author"}}],"book":{"id":1374,"pubplace":"Paris","publisher":"Les Belles Lettres","series":"","volume":"","edition_no":"","valid_from":null,"valid_until":null},"booksection":null,"article":null},"sort":[1965]}

The Conflict between Paganism and Christianity in the Fourth Century, 1963
By: Momigliano, Arnaldo
Title The Conflict between Paganism and Christianity in the Fourth Century
Type Monograph
Language English
Date 1963
Publication Place Oxford
Publisher Oxford University Press
Categories no categories
Author(s) Momigliano, Arnaldo
Editor(s)
Translator(s)
The relations between Paganism and Christianity in the fourth century seemed a suitable theme for a course of lectures at the Warburg Institute. The eight lectures here collected were delivered in the academic year 1958-9 and are published as they were delivered. It was, however, considered expedient to translate into English the two lectures which were given in French and the one which was in German.. The lecturers were left free to choose their own subject and to add the notes they wanted for publication. Specialists will judge each paper on its individual merits. For the general reader I have added, by way of introduction, a few pages on the problem of Christianity and the decline of the Roman empire. They were originally part of the two Taft Lectures which I delivered in the University of Cincinnati in 1959. A. M." [preface]

{"_index":"sire","_type":"_doc","_id":"182","_score":null,"_source":{"id":182,"authors_free":[{"id":238,"entry_id":182,"agent_type":null,"is_normalised":null,"person_id":516,"institution_id":null,"role":{"id":1,"role_name":"author"},"free_name":"Momigliano, Arnaldo","free_first_name":"Arnaldo","free_last_name":"Momigliano","norm_person":{"id":516,"first_name":"Arnaldo","last_name":"Momigliano","full_name":"Momigliano, Arnaldo","short_ident":"","is_classical_name":null,"dnb_url":"http:\/\/d-nb.info\/gnd\/119059843","viaf_url":"","db_url":"","from_claudius":null}}],"entry_title":"The Conflict between Paganism and Christianity in the Fourth Century","main_title":{"title":"The Conflict between Paganism and Christianity in the Fourth Century"},"abstract":"The relations between Paganism and Christianity in the fourth century seemed a suitable theme for a course of lectures at the Warburg Institute. The eight lectures here collected were delivered in the academic year 1958-9 and are published as they were delivered. It was, however, considered expedient to translate into English the two lectures which were given in French and the one which was in German.. The lecturers were left free to choose their own subject and to add the notes they wanted for publication. Specialists will judge each paper on its individual merits. For the general reader I have added, by way of introduction, a few pages on the problem of Christianity and the decline of the Roman empire. They were originally part of the two Taft Lectures which I delivered in the University of Cincinnati in 1959. A. M.\" [preface]","btype":1,"date":"1963","language":"English","online_url":"","online_resources":"https:\/\/uni-koeln.sciebo.de\/s\/ztVhur4G6ufes1n","doi_url":null,"categories":[],"authors":[{"id":516,"full_name":"Momigliano, Arnaldo","role":{"id":1,"role_name":"author"}}],"book":{"id":182,"pubplace":"Oxford","publisher":"Oxford University Press ","series":"","volume":"","edition_no":"","valid_from":null,"valid_until":null},"booksection":null,"article":null},"sort":[1963]}

Der Metaphysikbegriff in den Aristoteleskommentaren der Ammoniusschule, 1961
By: Kremer, Klaus
Title Der Metaphysikbegriff in den Aristoteleskommentaren der Ammoniusschule
Type Monograph
Language German
Date 1961
Publication Place Münster
Publisher Aschendorff
Series Beiträge zur Geschichte der Philosophie und Theologie des Mittelalters
Volume 39.1
Categories no categories
Author(s) Kremer, Klaus
Editor(s)
Translator(s)

{"_index":"sire","_type":"_doc","_id":"68","_score":null,"_source":{"id":68,"authors_free":[{"id":76,"entry_id":68,"agent_type":null,"is_normalised":null,"person_id":440,"institution_id":null,"role":{"id":1,"role_name":"author"},"free_name":"Kremer, Klaus","free_first_name":"Klaus","free_last_name":"Kremer","norm_person":{"id":440,"first_name":"Klaus","last_name":"Kremer","full_name":"Kremer, Klaus","short_ident":"","is_classical_name":null,"dnb_url":"http:\/\/d-nb.info\/gnd\/120476452","viaf_url":"","db_url":"","from_claudius":null}}],"entry_title":"Der Metaphysikbegriff in den Aristoteleskommentaren der Ammoniusschule","main_title":{"title":"Der Metaphysikbegriff in den Aristoteleskommentaren der Ammoniusschule"},"abstract":"","btype":1,"date":"1961","language":"German","online_url":"","online_resources":"https:\/\/uni-koeln.sciebo.de\/s\/V6mUOryd1wbPedB","doi_url":null,"categories":[],"authors":[{"id":440,"full_name":"Kremer, Klaus","role":{"id":1,"role_name":"author"}}],"book":{"id":68,"pubplace":"M\u00fcnster","publisher":"Aschendorff","series":"Beitr\u00e4ge zur Geschichte der Philosophie und Theologie des Mittelalters","volume":"39.1","edition_no":"","valid_from":null,"valid_until":null},"booksection":null,"article":null},"sort":[1961]}

Anaximander and the origins of Greek cosmology, 1960
By: Kahn, Charles H.
Title Anaximander and the origins of Greek cosmology
Type Monograph
Language English
Date 1960
Publication Place New York
Publisher Columbia University Press
Categories no categories
Author(s) Kahn, Charles H.
Editor(s)
Translator(s)
Reconstructs the pattern of Anaximander's thought, through a criticism and analysis of ancient traditions. Discusses the evidence for Anaximander's views and how this contributed to his observations of the universe.

{"_index":"sire","_type":"_doc","_id":"151","_score":null,"_source":{"id":151,"authors_free":[{"id":191,"entry_id":151,"agent_type":null,"is_normalised":null,"person_id":530,"institution_id":null,"role":{"id":1,"role_name":"author"},"free_name":"Kahn, Charles H.","free_first_name":"Charles H.","free_last_name":"Kahn","norm_person":{"id":530,"first_name":"Charles H.","last_name":"Kahn","full_name":"Kahn, Charles H.","short_ident":"","is_classical_name":null,"dnb_url":"http:\/\/d-nb.info\/gnd\/129468444","viaf_url":"","db_url":"","from_claudius":null}}],"entry_title":"Anaximander and the origins of Greek cosmology","main_title":{"title":"Anaximander and the origins of Greek cosmology"},"abstract":"Reconstructs the pattern of Anaximander's thought, through a criticism and analysis of ancient traditions. Discusses the evidence for Anaximander's views and how this contributed to his observations of the universe.","btype":1,"date":"1960","language":"English","online_url":"","online_resources":"https:\/\/uni-koeln.sciebo.de\/s\/Amc3UdOTdHqBeZB","doi_url":null,"categories":[],"authors":[{"id":530,"full_name":"Kahn, Charles H.","role":{"id":1,"role_name":"author"}}],"book":{"id":151,"pubplace":"New York","publisher":"Columbia University Press","series":"","volume":"","edition_no":"","valid_from":null,"valid_until":null},"booksection":null,"article":null},"sort":[1960]}

Saggi sull'aristotelismo padovano: dal secolo XIV al XVI, 1958
By: Nardi, Bruno
Title Saggi sull'aristotelismo padovano: dal secolo XIV al XVI
Type Monograph
Language Italian
Date 1958
Publication Place Firenze
Publisher Sansoni
Series Studi sulla tradizione aristotelica nel Veneto
Categories no categories
Author(s) Nardi, Bruno
Editor(s)
Translator(s)

{"_index":"sire","_type":"_doc","_id":"1454","_score":null,"_source":{"id":1454,"authors_free":[{"id":2465,"entry_id":1454,"agent_type":"person","is_normalised":1,"person_id":493,"institution_id":null,"role":{"id":1,"role_name":"author"},"free_name":"Nardi, Bruno","free_first_name":"Bruno","free_last_name":"Nardi","norm_person":{"id":493,"first_name":"Bruno","last_name":"Nardi","full_name":"Nardi, Bruno","short_ident":"","is_classical_name":null,"dnb_url":"http:\/\/d-nb.info\/gnd\/119470691","viaf_url":"","db_url":"","from_claudius":null}}],"entry_title":"Saggi sull'aristotelismo padovano: dal secolo XIV al XVI","main_title":{"title":"Saggi sull'aristotelismo padovano: dal secolo XIV al XVI"},"abstract":"","btype":1,"date":"1958","language":"Italian","online_url":"http:\/\/zotero.org\/groups\/313293\/items\/NAC2A3GA","online_resources":"https:\/\/uni-koeln.sciebo.de\/s\/EUOhjNAanQcAWDc","doi_url":null,"categories":[],"authors":[{"id":493,"full_name":"Nardi, Bruno","role":{"id":1,"role_name":"author"}}],"book":{"id":1454,"pubplace":"Firenze","publisher":"Sansoni","series":"Studi sulla tradizione aristotelica nel Veneto","volume":"","edition_no":"","valid_from":null,"valid_until":null},"booksection":null,"article":null},"sort":[1958]}

  • PAGE 1 OF 1
Anaximander and the origins of Greek cosmology, 1960
By: Kahn, Charles H.
Title Anaximander and the origins of Greek cosmology
Type Monograph
Language English
Date 1960
Publication Place New York
Publisher Columbia University Press
Categories no categories
Author(s) Kahn, Charles H.
Editor(s)
Translator(s)
Reconstructs the pattern of Anaximander's thought, through a criticism and analysis of ancient traditions. Discusses the evidence for Anaximander's views and how this contributed to his observations of the universe.

{"_index":"sire","_type":"_doc","_id":"151","_score":null,"_source":{"id":151,"authors_free":[{"id":191,"entry_id":151,"agent_type":null,"is_normalised":null,"person_id":530,"institution_id":null,"role":{"id":1,"role_name":"author"},"free_name":"Kahn, Charles H.","free_first_name":"Charles H.","free_last_name":"Kahn","norm_person":{"id":530,"first_name":"Charles H.","last_name":"Kahn","full_name":"Kahn, Charles H.","short_ident":"","is_classical_name":null,"dnb_url":"http:\/\/d-nb.info\/gnd\/129468444","viaf_url":"","db_url":"","from_claudius":null}}],"entry_title":"Anaximander and the origins of Greek cosmology","main_title":{"title":"Anaximander and the origins of Greek cosmology"},"abstract":"Reconstructs the pattern of Anaximander's thought, through a criticism and analysis of ancient traditions. Discusses the evidence for Anaximander's views and how this contributed to his observations of the universe.","btype":1,"date":"1960","language":"English","online_url":"","online_resources":"https:\/\/uni-koeln.sciebo.de\/s\/Amc3UdOTdHqBeZB","doi_url":null,"categories":[],"authors":[{"id":530,"full_name":"Kahn, Charles H.","role":{"id":1,"role_name":"author"}}],"book":{"id":151,"pubplace":"New York","publisher":"Columbia University Press","series":"","volume":"","edition_no":"","valid_from":null,"valid_until":null},"booksection":null,"article":null},"sort":["Anaximander and the origins of Greek cosmology"]}

Aristote, Du ciel. Texte établi et traduit par Paul Moraux, 1965
By: Moraux, Paul, Aristote
Title Aristote, Du ciel. Texte établi et traduit par Paul Moraux
Type Monograph
Language French
Date 1965
Publication Place Paris
Publisher Les Belles Lettres
Categories no categories
Author(s) Moraux, Paul , Aristote
Editor(s)
Translator(s)

{"_index":"sire","_type":"_doc","_id":"1374","_score":null,"_source":{"id":1374,"authors_free":[{"id":2084,"entry_id":1374,"agent_type":"person","is_normalised":1,"person_id":137,"institution_id":null,"role":{"id":1,"role_name":"author"},"free_name":"Moraux, Paul","free_first_name":"Paul","free_last_name":"Moraux","norm_person":{"id":137,"first_name":"Paul ","last_name":"Moraux","full_name":"Moraux, Paul ","short_ident":"","is_classical_name":null,"dnb_url":"http:\/\/d-nb.info\/gnd\/117755591","viaf_url":"","db_url":"","from_claudius":null}},{"id":2113,"entry_id":1374,"agent_type":"person","is_normalised":null,"person_id":263,"institution_id":null,"role":{"id":1,"role_name":"author"},"free_name":"Aristote","free_first_name":"","free_last_name":"","norm_person":{"id":263,"first_name":"","last_name":"","full_name":"Aristoteles","short_ident":"","is_classical_name":null,"dnb_url":"http:\/\/d-nb.info\/gnd\/118650130","viaf_url":"","db_url":"","from_claudius":null}}],"entry_title":"Aristote, Du ciel. Texte \u00e9tabli et traduit par Paul Moraux","main_title":{"title":"Aristote, Du ciel. Texte \u00e9tabli et traduit par Paul Moraux"},"abstract":"","btype":1,"date":"1965","language":"French","online_url":"","online_resources":"https:\/\/uni-koeln.sciebo.de\/s\/W0FrLs9BKUEyoH3","doi_url":null,"categories":[],"authors":[{"id":137,"full_name":"Moraux, Paul ","role":{"id":1,"role_name":"author"}},{"id":263,"full_name":"Aristoteles","role":{"id":1,"role_name":"author"}}],"book":{"id":1374,"pubplace":"Paris","publisher":"Les Belles Lettres","series":"","volume":"","edition_no":"","valid_from":null,"valid_until":null},"booksection":null,"article":null},"sort":["Aristote, Du ciel. Texte \u00e9tabli et traduit par Paul Moraux"]}

Das Corollarium de Tempore des Simplikios und die Aporien des Aristoteles zur Zeit, 1969
By: Meyer, Hubert 
Title Das Corollarium de Tempore des Simplikios und die Aporien des Aristoteles zur Zeit
Type Monograph
Language German
Date 1969
Publication Place Meisenheim am Glan
Publisher Anton Hain
Series Monographien zur Naturphilosophie
Volume 8
Categories no categories
Author(s) Meyer, Hubert 
Editor(s)
Translator(s)
Review: In recent years, there has been a renewed interest in the period of Greek philosophy after Aristotle. Since ancient Greek thought exhibits unbroken continuity, the commentaries on Aristotle from late antiquity retain an authenticity and value for the study of Aristotle himself, which have not always been sufficiently recognized. This extensive and learned work is a study of time as presented by Simplicius in his commentary on Aristotle's Physics and in the Doubts and Solutions of Simplicius' teacher, Damascius. It sheds new light not only on the Neoplatonic philosophy of time but also on the notorious "difficulties" of Aristotle regarding time.
The work presents a significant amount of philosophical argument, often complex and subtle. Therefore, some oversimplification is necessary. Damascius and Simplicius utilize materials from two different philosophies of time: Aristotle's and Plotinus'. Aristotle's view is that time is the number of motion according to before and after, based on the phenomenon of regular and endless physical motion. Although number, in Aristotle, is a mathematical abstraction, time, being a number, is not merely ideal or mathematical but is actually verified in the physical world. Soul or mind is needed to make the before-and-after of physical motion actually numbered. The "matter" of time, the endless motion of nature (especially the heavens), is real, not merely ideal or mathematical. The form of time is determined by the real relation of before and after, making time a real category, one of the modes of being. Time is the way of being whose being consists in becoming.
The other philosophy of time influencing Damascius and Simplicius is the more "idealist" Neoplatonic one, which bases time on the soul. According to Plotinus, the number of motion is an applied number. Eternity is the life of mind (nous), and time is the life of the world-soul. Numbers exist in the realm of mind or being or ideal forms, the second hypostasis of Plotinus. When mind descends into body, constituting soul or the third hypostasis, the life of mind or eternity becomes an activity of soul or time. Time is a psychic measuring, corresponding to Augustine's definition of time as a disrensio animae.
Simplicius, like other ancient and medieval commentators, aims not only at a scholarly reconstruction of Aristotle's "difficulties" but at a real solution to the philosophical problem of time. The commentator's new and original philosophy emerges during the exposition of Aristotle's text. Simplicius' thesis is that the reality of time is the present moment, or now, or point of time, which is endlessly repeated. However, this cannot be a correct commentary on Aristotle, for whom time is solidly based on real physical motion. Simplicius' view of time is more abstract since he overlooks the reality of motion.
The central part of Meyer's book examines in detail the philosophy of time in the Greek text of the Corollarium. Simplicius' view is that time is in becoming, not in being or eternity. Time's being is in becoming, and the only being in becoming is the "now," which makes time the "now." Simplicius contrasts this with his more Platonic teacher, Damascius, for whom eternity, to aei, or the realm of being, contains a form of time, a supra-temporal whole-time, or time-number, or mathematical "time," the unenfolded structure of number, which, in turn, contains time or continual becoming.
Simplicius replies in a more Aristotelian fashion, arguing that Damascius' region of the "always" or "ever" of time, or time as a whole, is entirely unnecessary. Time flows infinitely, an always-becoming, but this infinity of time is not an actual whole. Time flows into infinity, but there is no actual infinite or eternal whole, as personified by Damascius' Demiourgos.
Simplicius' interpretation is part of the wider movement of thought in later antiquity when time as the number of motion is forgotten and replaced by a more abstract definition.
The interest in these thinkers, Damascius and Simplicius, lies in their providing us with variants or subspecies of the two great masters, Plato and Aristotle. Meyer's learned work makes these obscure texts widely accessible, and his interpretations of the rich material are cautious and sound. The presentation is not [iir die Menge; and, it is sometimes not very clear just what Greek distinctions are being noted by certain G e r m a n distinctions. There are misprints in French, G e r m a n, and Greek. The work is a fine contribution to scholarship.
PAUL J. W. MILLER

{"_index":"sire","_type":"_doc","_id":"66","_score":null,"_source":{"id":66,"authors_free":[{"id":74,"entry_id":66,"agent_type":null,"is_normalised":null,"person_id":441,"institution_id":null,"role":{"id":1,"role_name":"author"},"free_name":"Meyer, Hubert\u00a0","free_first_name":"Hubert","free_last_name":"Meyer","norm_person":{"id":441,"first_name":"Hubert","last_name":"Meyer","full_name":"Meyer, Hubert\u00a0","short_ident":"","is_classical_name":null,"dnb_url":"","viaf_url":"","db_url":"","from_claudius":null}}],"entry_title":"Das Corollarium de Tempore des Simplikios und die Aporien des Aristoteles zur Zeit","main_title":{"title":"Das Corollarium de Tempore des Simplikios und die Aporien des Aristoteles zur Zeit"},"abstract":"Review: In recent years, there has been a renewed interest in the period of Greek philosophy after Aristotle. Since ancient Greek thought exhibits unbroken continuity, the commentaries on Aristotle from late antiquity retain an authenticity and value for the study of Aristotle himself, which have not always been sufficiently recognized. This extensive and learned work is a study of time as presented by Simplicius in his commentary on Aristotle's Physics and in the Doubts and Solutions of Simplicius' teacher, Damascius. It sheds new light not only on the Neoplatonic philosophy of time but also on the notorious \"difficulties\" of Aristotle regarding time.\r\nThe work presents a significant amount of philosophical argument, often complex and subtle. Therefore, some oversimplification is necessary. Damascius and Simplicius utilize materials from two different philosophies of time: Aristotle's and Plotinus'. Aristotle's view is that time is the number of motion according to before and after, based on the phenomenon of regular and endless physical motion. Although number, in Aristotle, is a mathematical abstraction, time, being a number, is not merely ideal or mathematical but is actually verified in the physical world. Soul or mind is needed to make the before-and-after of physical motion actually numbered. The \"matter\" of time, the endless motion of nature (especially the heavens), is real, not merely ideal or mathematical. The form of time is determined by the real relation of before and after, making time a real category, one of the modes of being. Time is the way of being whose being consists in becoming.\r\nThe other philosophy of time influencing Damascius and Simplicius is the more \"idealist\" Neoplatonic one, which bases time on the soul. According to Plotinus, the number of motion is an applied number. Eternity is the life of mind (nous), and time is the life of the world-soul. Numbers exist in the realm of mind or being or ideal forms, the second hypostasis of Plotinus. When mind descends into body, constituting soul or the third hypostasis, the life of mind or eternity becomes an activity of soul or time. Time is a psychic measuring, corresponding to Augustine's definition of time as a disrensio animae.\r\nSimplicius, like other ancient and medieval commentators, aims not only at a scholarly reconstruction of Aristotle's \"difficulties\" but at a real solution to the philosophical problem of time. The commentator's new and original philosophy emerges during the exposition of Aristotle's text. Simplicius' thesis is that the reality of time is the present moment, or now, or point of time, which is endlessly repeated. However, this cannot be a correct commentary on Aristotle, for whom time is solidly based on real physical motion. Simplicius' view of time is more abstract since he overlooks the reality of motion.\r\nThe central part of Meyer's book examines in detail the philosophy of time in the Greek text of the Corollarium. Simplicius' view is that time is in becoming, not in being or eternity. Time's being is in becoming, and the only being in becoming is the \"now,\" which makes time the \"now.\" Simplicius contrasts this with his more Platonic teacher, Damascius, for whom eternity, to aei, or the realm of being, contains a form of time, a supra-temporal whole-time, or time-number, or mathematical \"time,\" the unenfolded structure of number, which, in turn, contains time or continual becoming.\r\nSimplicius replies in a more Aristotelian fashion, arguing that Damascius' region of the \"always\" or \"ever\" of time, or time as a whole, is entirely unnecessary. Time flows infinitely, an always-becoming, but this infinity of time is not an actual whole. Time flows into infinity, but there is no actual infinite or eternal whole, as personified by Damascius' Demiourgos.\r\nSimplicius' interpretation is part of the wider movement of thought in later antiquity when time as the number of motion is forgotten and replaced by a more abstract definition.\r\nThe interest in these thinkers, Damascius and Simplicius, lies in their providing us with variants or subspecies of the two great masters, Plato and Aristotle. Meyer's learned work makes these obscure texts widely accessible, and his interpretations of the rich material are cautious and sound. The presentation is not [iir die Menge; and, it is sometimes not very clear just what Greek distinctions are being noted by certain G e r m a n distinctions. There are misprints in French, G e r m a n, and Greek. The work is a fine contribution to scholarship.\r\nPAUL J. W. MILLER\r\n","btype":1,"date":"1969","language":"German","online_url":"","online_resources":"https:\/\/uni-koeln.sciebo.de\/s\/f9MAopVd91xU5pu","doi_url":null,"categories":[],"authors":[{"id":441,"full_name":"Meyer, Hubert\u00a0","role":{"id":1,"role_name":"author"}}],"book":{"id":66,"pubplace":"Meisenheim am Glan","publisher":"Anton Hain","series":"Monographien zur Naturphilosophie","volume":"8","edition_no":"","valid_from":null,"valid_until":null},"booksection":null,"article":null},"sort":["Das Corollarium de Tempore des Simplikios und die Aporien des Aristoteles zur Zeit"]}

Der Metaphysikbegriff in den Aristoteleskommentaren der Ammoniusschule, 1961
By: Kremer, Klaus
Title Der Metaphysikbegriff in den Aristoteleskommentaren der Ammoniusschule
Type Monograph
Language German
Date 1961
Publication Place Münster
Publisher Aschendorff
Series Beiträge zur Geschichte der Philosophie und Theologie des Mittelalters
Volume 39.1
Categories no categories
Author(s) Kremer, Klaus
Editor(s)
Translator(s)

{"_index":"sire","_type":"_doc","_id":"68","_score":null,"_source":{"id":68,"authors_free":[{"id":76,"entry_id":68,"agent_type":null,"is_normalised":null,"person_id":440,"institution_id":null,"role":{"id":1,"role_name":"author"},"free_name":"Kremer, Klaus","free_first_name":"Klaus","free_last_name":"Kremer","norm_person":{"id":440,"first_name":"Klaus","last_name":"Kremer","full_name":"Kremer, Klaus","short_ident":"","is_classical_name":null,"dnb_url":"http:\/\/d-nb.info\/gnd\/120476452","viaf_url":"","db_url":"","from_claudius":null}}],"entry_title":"Der Metaphysikbegriff in den Aristoteleskommentaren der Ammoniusschule","main_title":{"title":"Der Metaphysikbegriff in den Aristoteleskommentaren der Ammoniusschule"},"abstract":"","btype":1,"date":"1961","language":"German","online_url":"","online_resources":"https:\/\/uni-koeln.sciebo.de\/s\/V6mUOryd1wbPedB","doi_url":null,"categories":[],"authors":[{"id":440,"full_name":"Kremer, Klaus","role":{"id":1,"role_name":"author"}}],"book":{"id":68,"pubplace":"M\u00fcnster","publisher":"Aschendorff","series":"Beitr\u00e4ge zur Geschichte der Philosophie und Theologie des Mittelalters","volume":"39.1","edition_no":"","valid_from":null,"valid_until":null},"booksection":null,"article":null},"sort":["Der Metaphysikbegriff in den Aristoteleskommentaren der Ammoniusschule"]}

Saggi sull'aristotelismo padovano: dal secolo XIV al XVI, 1958
By: Nardi, Bruno
Title Saggi sull'aristotelismo padovano: dal secolo XIV al XVI
Type Monograph
Language Italian
Date 1958
Publication Place Firenze
Publisher Sansoni
Series Studi sulla tradizione aristotelica nel Veneto
Categories no categories
Author(s) Nardi, Bruno
Editor(s)
Translator(s)

{"_index":"sire","_type":"_doc","_id":"1454","_score":null,"_source":{"id":1454,"authors_free":[{"id":2465,"entry_id":1454,"agent_type":"person","is_normalised":1,"person_id":493,"institution_id":null,"role":{"id":1,"role_name":"author"},"free_name":"Nardi, Bruno","free_first_name":"Bruno","free_last_name":"Nardi","norm_person":{"id":493,"first_name":"Bruno","last_name":"Nardi","full_name":"Nardi, Bruno","short_ident":"","is_classical_name":null,"dnb_url":"http:\/\/d-nb.info\/gnd\/119470691","viaf_url":"","db_url":"","from_claudius":null}}],"entry_title":"Saggi sull'aristotelismo padovano: dal secolo XIV al XVI","main_title":{"title":"Saggi sull'aristotelismo padovano: dal secolo XIV al XVI"},"abstract":"","btype":1,"date":"1958","language":"Italian","online_url":"http:\/\/zotero.org\/groups\/313293\/items\/NAC2A3GA","online_resources":"https:\/\/uni-koeln.sciebo.de\/s\/EUOhjNAanQcAWDc","doi_url":null,"categories":[],"authors":[{"id":493,"full_name":"Nardi, Bruno","role":{"id":1,"role_name":"author"}}],"book":{"id":1454,"pubplace":"Firenze","publisher":"Sansoni","series":"Studi sulla tradizione aristotelica nel Veneto","volume":"","edition_no":"","valid_from":null,"valid_until":null},"booksection":null,"article":null},"sort":["Saggi sull'aristotelismo padovano: dal secolo XIV al XVI"]}

The Conflict between Paganism and Christianity in the Fourth Century, 1963
By: Momigliano, Arnaldo
Title The Conflict between Paganism and Christianity in the Fourth Century
Type Monograph
Language English
Date 1963
Publication Place Oxford
Publisher Oxford University Press
Categories no categories
Author(s) Momigliano, Arnaldo
Editor(s)
Translator(s)
The relations between Paganism and Christianity in the fourth century seemed a suitable theme for a course of lectures at the Warburg Institute. The eight lectures here collected were delivered in the academic year 1958-9 and are published as they were delivered. It was, however, considered expedient to translate into English the two lectures which were given in French and the one which was in German.. The lecturers were left free to choose their own subject and to add the notes they wanted for publication. Specialists will judge each paper on its individual merits. For the general reader I have added, by way of introduction, a few pages on the problem of Christianity and the decline of the Roman empire. They were originally part of the two Taft Lectures which I delivered in the University of Cincinnati in 1959. A. M." [preface]

{"_index":"sire","_type":"_doc","_id":"182","_score":null,"_source":{"id":182,"authors_free":[{"id":238,"entry_id":182,"agent_type":null,"is_normalised":null,"person_id":516,"institution_id":null,"role":{"id":1,"role_name":"author"},"free_name":"Momigliano, Arnaldo","free_first_name":"Arnaldo","free_last_name":"Momigliano","norm_person":{"id":516,"first_name":"Arnaldo","last_name":"Momigliano","full_name":"Momigliano, Arnaldo","short_ident":"","is_classical_name":null,"dnb_url":"http:\/\/d-nb.info\/gnd\/119059843","viaf_url":"","db_url":"","from_claudius":null}}],"entry_title":"The Conflict between Paganism and Christianity in the Fourth Century","main_title":{"title":"The Conflict between Paganism and Christianity in the Fourth Century"},"abstract":"The relations between Paganism and Christianity in the fourth century seemed a suitable theme for a course of lectures at the Warburg Institute. The eight lectures here collected were delivered in the academic year 1958-9 and are published as they were delivered. It was, however, considered expedient to translate into English the two lectures which were given in French and the one which was in German.. The lecturers were left free to choose their own subject and to add the notes they wanted for publication. Specialists will judge each paper on its individual merits. For the general reader I have added, by way of introduction, a few pages on the problem of Christianity and the decline of the Roman empire. They were originally part of the two Taft Lectures which I delivered in the University of Cincinnati in 1959. A. M.\" [preface]","btype":1,"date":"1963","language":"English","online_url":"","online_resources":"https:\/\/uni-koeln.sciebo.de\/s\/ztVhur4G6ufes1n","doi_url":null,"categories":[],"authors":[{"id":516,"full_name":"Momigliano, Arnaldo","role":{"id":1,"role_name":"author"}}],"book":{"id":182,"pubplace":"Oxford","publisher":"Oxford University Press ","series":"","volume":"","edition_no":"","valid_from":null,"valid_until":null},"booksection":null,"article":null},"sort":["The Conflict between Paganism and Christianity in the Fourth Century"]}

The Renaissance discovery of classical antiquity, 1969
By: Weiss, Roberto
Title The Renaissance discovery of classical antiquity
Type Monograph
Language English
Date 1969
Publication Place Oxford – New York
Publisher Blackwell
Categories no categories
Author(s) Weiss, Roberto
Editor(s)
Translator(s)
The author traces the rise of a new attitude to classical antiquity, an attitude which became noticeable in the late 13th century but which came fully of age in the first half of the 15th century with humanists such as Poggio and Flavio Biodon. The book covers the period 1300 to 1527. [offical abstract]

{"_index":"sire","_type":"_doc","_id":"191","_score":null,"_source":{"id":191,"authors_free":[{"id":247,"entry_id":191,"agent_type":null,"is_normalised":null,"person_id":533,"institution_id":null,"role":{"id":1,"role_name":"author"},"free_name":"Weiss, Roberto","free_first_name":"Roberto","free_last_name":"Weiss","norm_person":{"id":533,"first_name":"Roberto","last_name":"Weiss","full_name":"Weiss, Roberto","short_ident":"","is_classical_name":null,"dnb_url":"http:\/\/d-nb.info\/gnd\/129054968","viaf_url":"","db_url":"","from_claudius":null}}],"entry_title":"The Renaissance discovery of classical antiquity","main_title":{"title":"The Renaissance discovery of classical antiquity"},"abstract":"The author traces the rise of a new attitude to classical antiquity, an attitude which became noticeable in the late 13th century but which came fully of age in the first half of the 15th century with humanists such as Poggio and Flavio Biodon. The book covers the period 1300 to 1527. [offical abstract]","btype":1,"date":"1969","language":"English","online_url":"","online_resources":"https:\/\/uni-koeln.sciebo.de\/s\/hWocUhaP31pptJ7","doi_url":null,"categories":[],"authors":[{"id":533,"full_name":"Weiss, Roberto","role":{"id":1,"role_name":"author"}}],"book":{"id":191,"pubplace":"Oxford \u2013 \tNew York","publisher":"Blackwell","series":"","volume":"","edition_no":null,"valid_from":null,"valid_until":null},"booksection":null,"article":null},"sort":["The Renaissance discovery of classical antiquity"]}

ΠΕΡΙ ΦΥΣΕΩΣ: Zur Frühgeschichte der Buchtitel, 1970
By: Schmalzriedt, Egidius
Title ΠΕΡΙ ΦΥΣΕΩΣ: Zur Frühgeschichte der Buchtitel
Type Monograph
Language German
Date 1970
Publication Place München
Publisher Fink
Categories no categories
Author(s) Schmalzriedt, Egidius
Editor(s)
Translator(s)

{"_index":"sire","_type":"_doc","_id":"58","_score":null,"_source":{"id":58,"authors_free":[{"id":66,"entry_id":58,"agent_type":null,"is_normalised":null,"person_id":534,"institution_id":null,"role":{"id":1,"role_name":"author"},"free_name":"Schmalzriedt, Egidius","free_first_name":"Egidius","free_last_name":"Schmalzriedt","norm_person":{"id":534,"first_name":"Egidius","last_name":"Schmalzriedt","full_name":"Schmalzriedt, Egidius","short_ident":"","is_classical_name":null,"dnb_url":"http:\/\/d-nb.info\/gnd\/123026261","viaf_url":"","db_url":"","from_claudius":null}}],"entry_title":"\u03a0\u0395\u03a1\u0399 \u03a6\u03a5\u03a3\u0395\u03a9\u03a3: Zur Fr\u00fchgeschichte der Buchtitel","main_title":{"title":"\u03a0\u0395\u03a1\u0399 \u03a6\u03a5\u03a3\u0395\u03a9\u03a3: Zur Fr\u00fchgeschichte der Buchtitel"},"abstract":"","btype":1,"date":"1970","language":"German","online_url":"","online_resources":"https:\/\/uni-koeln.sciebo.de\/s\/jDt8nqgkEW6wFPO","doi_url":null,"categories":[],"authors":[{"id":534,"full_name":"Schmalzriedt, Egidius","role":{"id":1,"role_name":"author"}}],"book":{"id":58,"pubplace":"M\u00fcnchen","publisher":"Fink","series":"","volume":"","edition_no":null,"valid_from":null,"valid_until":null},"booksection":null,"article":null},"sort":["\u03a0\u0395\u03a1\u0399 \u03a6\u03a5\u03a3\u0395\u03a9\u03a3: Zur Fr\u00fchgeschichte der Buchtitel"]}

  • PAGE 1 OF 1