Title | Zur Entstehung und zum Wesen des griechischen wissenschaftlichen Kommentars |
Type | Article |
Language | German |
Date | 1932 |
Journal | Hermes |
Volume | 67 |
Issue | 4 |
Pages | 397-412 |
Categories | no categories |
Author(s) | Geffcken, Johannes |
Editor(s) | |
Translator(s) |
In dem Text wird die Entstehung und das Wesen des antiken Kommentars untersucht. Es wird aufgezeigt, dass der Kommentar in der Antike als eine Art praktische Notwendigkeit angesehen wurde, sei es in Form von Erklärungen zu sakralen Gesetzen, Schulunterricht oder Homerparaphrasen. Die Aristotelische Schule beeinflusste den Geist aller wissenschaftlichen Kommentare. Der Autor schlägt vor, dass eine wirkliche Geschichte des antiken Kommentars notwendig ist, um die Kontinuität und die individuellen Beiträge der Forscher und Denker zu verstehen. [introduction/conclusion] |
Online Resources | https://uni-koeln.sciebo.de/s/lev9vfokt9KpzHD |
{"_index":"sire","_type":"_doc","_id":"1314","_score":null,"_source":{"id":1314,"authors_free":[{"id":1948,"entry_id":1314,"agent_type":"person","is_normalised":1,"person_id":126,"institution_id":null,"role":{"id":1,"role_name":"author"},"free_name":"Geffcken, Johannes","free_first_name":"Johannes","free_last_name":"Geffcken","norm_person":{"id":126,"first_name":"Johannes","last_name":"Geffcken","full_name":"Geffcken, Johannes","short_ident":"","is_classical_name":null,"dnb_url":"http:\/\/d-nb.info\/gnd\/120376644","viaf_url":"","db_url":"","from_claudius":null}}],"entry_title":"Zur Entstehung und zum Wesen des griechischen wissenschaftlichen Kommentars","main_title":{"title":"Zur Entstehung und zum Wesen des griechischen wissenschaftlichen Kommentars"},"abstract":"In dem Text wird die Entstehung und das Wesen des antiken Kommentars untersucht. Es wird aufgezeigt, dass der Kommentar in der Antike als eine Art praktische Notwendigkeit angesehen wurde, sei es in Form von Erkl\u00e4rungen zu sakralen Gesetzen, Schulunterricht oder Homerparaphrasen. Die Aristotelische Schule beeinflusste den Geist aller wissenschaftlichen Kommentare. Der Autor schl\u00e4gt vor, dass eine wirkliche Geschichte des antiken Kommentars notwendig ist, um die Kontinuit\u00e4t und die individuellen Beitr\u00e4ge der Forscher und Denker zu verstehen. [introduction\/conclusion]","btype":3,"date":"1932","language":"German","online_url":"","online_resources":"https:\/\/uni-koeln.sciebo.de\/s\/lev9vfokt9KpzHD","doi_url":null,"categories":[],"authors":[{"id":126,"full_name":"Geffcken, Johannes","role":{"id":1,"role_name":"author"}}],"book":null,"booksection":null,"article":{"id":1314,"journal_id":null,"journal_name":"Hermes","volume":"67","issue":"4","pages":"397-412"}},"sort":[1932]}
Title | The Parmenides of Plato and the Origin of the Neoplatonic 'One' |
Type | Article |
Language | English |
Date | 1928 |
Journal | Classical Quarterly |
Volume | 22 |
Issue | 3/4 (Jul. - Oct., 1928), |
Pages | 129–142 |
Categories | no categories |
Author(s) | Dodds, Eric R. |
Editor(s) | |
Translator(s) |
THE last phase of Greek philosophy has until recently been less intelli- gently studied than any other, and in our understanding of its development there are still lamentable lacunae. Three errors in particular have in the past prevented a proper appreciation of Plotinus' place in the history of philosophy. When this false trail was at length abandoned the fashion for orientalizing explanations persisted in another guise: to the earliest historians of Neo- platonism, Simon and Vacherot, the school of Plotinus was (in defiance of geographical facts) 'the school of Alexandria,' and its inspiration was mainly Egyptian. Vacherot says of Neoplatonism that it is 'essentially and radically oriental, having nothing of Greek thought but its language and procedure.' Few would be found to-day to subscribe to so sweeping a pronouncement; but the existence of an important oriental element in Plotinus' thought is still affirmed by many French and German writers. [p. 129] |
Online Resources | https://uni-koeln.sciebo.de/s/ElUfvVkaaeLIJVk |
{"_index":"sire","_type":"_doc","_id":"554","_score":null,"_source":{"id":554,"authors_free":[{"id":783,"entry_id":554,"agent_type":null,"is_normalised":null,"person_id":65,"institution_id":null,"role":{"id":1,"role_name":"author"},"free_name":"Dodds, Eric R. ","free_first_name":"Eric R. ","free_last_name":"Dodds","norm_person":{"id":65,"first_name":"Eric R. ","last_name":"Dodds","full_name":"Dodds, Eric R. ","short_ident":"","is_classical_name":null,"dnb_url":"http:\/\/d-nb.info\/gnd\/123026288","viaf_url":"","db_url":"","from_claudius":null}}],"entry_title":"The Parmenides of Plato and the Origin of the Neoplatonic 'One' ","main_title":{"title":"The Parmenides of Plato and the Origin of the Neoplatonic 'One' "},"abstract":"THE last phase of Greek philosophy has until recently been less intelli- \r\ngently studied than any other, and in our understanding of its development \r\nthere are still lamentable lacunae. Three errors in particular have in the past \r\nprevented a proper appreciation of Plotinus' place in the history of philosophy. When this false trail was at length abandoned the fashion for orientalizing \r\nexplanations persisted in another guise: to the earliest historians of Neo- \r\nplatonism, Simon and Vacherot, the school of Plotinus was (in defiance of \r\ngeographical facts) 'the school of Alexandria,' and its inspiration was mainly \r\nEgyptian. Vacherot says of Neoplatonism that it is 'essentially and radically \r\noriental, having nothing of Greek thought but its language and procedure.' \r\nFew would be found to-day to subscribe to so sweeping a pronouncement; but \r\nthe existence of an important oriental element in Plotinus' thought is still \r\naffirmed by many French and German writers. [p. 129]","btype":3,"date":"1928","language":"English","online_url":"","online_resources":"https:\/\/uni-koeln.sciebo.de\/s\/ElUfvVkaaeLIJVk","doi_url":null,"categories":[],"authors":[{"id":65,"full_name":"Dodds, Eric R. ","role":{"id":1,"role_name":"author"}}],"book":null,"booksection":null,"article":{"id":554,"journal_id":null,"journal_name":"Classical Quarterly","volume":"22","issue":"3\/4 (Jul. - Oct., 1928),","pages":"129\u2013142"}},"sort":[1928]}
Title | The Homoiomeries of Anaxagoras |
Type | Article |
Language | English |
Date | 1927 |
Journal | The Classical Quarterly |
Volume | 21 |
Issue | 3/4 |
Pages | 133-141 |
Categories | no categories |
Author(s) | Leon, Philip |
Editor(s) | |
Translator(s) |
[Conclusion, p. 141]: Anaxagoras does indeed, as he has been said to do, represent the culminating point of the enquiry into the one bto-tv. That simple enquiry for a simple unity becomes curiously complex, just because of the very simplicity and the thorough-going and uncompromising nature of Anaxagoras' logical mind. It has with him reached a stage where it must become transformed and pass on the one hand into logic in Plato, into the enquiry about the nature of predication through Gorgias and Antisthenes, and on the other hand into metaphysics, the theory of ideas, also in Plato. This central position of Anaxagoras is made clear by the passage discussed, according to which, I think, in considering the 'homoiomeries,' we should look upon parts as 'homoiomerous' primarily to the whole i~c6otov, and only secondarily to subordinate wholes. Indeed, it is implied in Anaxagoras' principle that there are only two entities which are properly wholes, the 0c0/cpo and voDv^. To call anything else a whole is more or less arbitrary, a principle not unworthy of the most thorough-going of modern absolutists. |
Online Resources | https://uni-koeln.sciebo.de/s/FXHNwY19loMmfLj |
{"_index":"sire","_type":"_doc","_id":"733","_score":null,"_source":{"id":733,"authors_free":[{"id":1096,"entry_id":733,"agent_type":null,"is_normalised":null,"person_id":245,"institution_id":null,"role":{"id":1,"role_name":"author"},"free_name":"Leon, Philip","free_first_name":"Philip","free_last_name":"Leon","norm_person":{"id":245,"first_name":"Philip","last_name":"Leon","full_name":"Leon, Philip","short_ident":"","is_classical_name":null,"dnb_url":"","viaf_url":"","db_url":"","from_claudius":null}}],"entry_title":"The Homoiomeries of Anaxagoras","main_title":{"title":"The Homoiomeries of Anaxagoras"},"abstract":"[Conclusion, p. 141]: Anaxagoras does indeed, as he has been said to do, represent the \r\nculminating point of the enquiry into the one bto-tv. That simple enquiry \r\nfor a simple unity becomes curiously complex, just because of the very \r\nsimplicity and the thorough-going and uncompromising nature of Anaxagoras' \r\nlogical mind. It has with him reached a stage where it must become \r\ntransformed and pass on the one hand into logic in Plato, into the enquiry \r\nabout the nature of predication through Gorgias and Antisthenes, and on the \r\nother hand into metaphysics, the theory of ideas, also in Plato. This central \r\nposition of Anaxagoras is made clear by the passage discussed, according \r\nto which, I think, in considering the 'homoiomeries,' we should look upon \r\nparts as 'homoiomerous' primarily to the whole i~c6otov, and only secondarily \r\nto subordinate wholes. Indeed, it is implied in Anaxagoras' principle that \r\nthere are only two entities which are properly wholes, the 0c0\/cpo and voDv^. To call anything else a whole is more or less arbitrary, a principle not \r\nunworthy of the most thorough-going of modern absolutists. ","btype":3,"date":"1927","language":"English","online_url":"","online_resources":"https:\/\/uni-koeln.sciebo.de\/s\/FXHNwY19loMmfLj","doi_url":null,"categories":[],"authors":[{"id":245,"full_name":"Leon, Philip","role":{"id":1,"role_name":"author"}}],"book":null,"booksection":null,"article":{"id":733,"journal_id":null,"journal_name":"The Classical Quarterly","volume":"21","issue":"3\/4","pages":"133-141"}},"sort":[1927]}
Title | Simpl. in Aristot. de Caelo p. 370, 29 ff. H |
Type | Article |
Language | German |
Date | 1924 |
Journal | Hermes |
Volume | 59 |
Issue | 1 |
Pages | 118-119 |
Categories | no categories |
Author(s) | Praechter, Karl |
Editor(s) | |
Translator(s) |
Online Resources | https://uni-koeln.sciebo.de/s/zc8efUUHCZuTFnA |
{"_index":"sire","_type":"_doc","_id":"1477","_score":null,"_source":{"id":1477,"authors_free":[{"id":2558,"entry_id":1477,"agent_type":"person","is_normalised":1,"person_id":293,"institution_id":null,"role":{"id":1,"role_name":"author"},"free_name":"Praechter, Karl","free_first_name":"Karl","free_last_name":"Praechter","norm_person":{"id":293,"first_name":"Karl","last_name":"Praechter","full_name":"Praechter, Karl","short_ident":"","is_classical_name":null,"dnb_url":"http:\/\/d-nb.info\/gnd\/116278609","viaf_url":"","db_url":"","from_claudius":null}}],"entry_title":"Simpl. in Aristot. de Caelo p. 370, 29 ff. H","main_title":{"title":"Simpl. in Aristot. de Caelo p. 370, 29 ff. H"},"abstract":"","btype":3,"date":"1924","language":"German","online_url":"","online_resources":"https:\/\/uni-koeln.sciebo.de\/s\/zc8efUUHCZuTFnA","doi_url":null,"categories":[],"authors":[{"id":293,"full_name":"Praechter, Karl","role":{"id":1,"role_name":"author"}}],"book":null,"booksection":null,"article":{"id":1477,"journal_id":null,"journal_name":"Hermes","volume":"59","issue":"1","pages":"118-119"}},"sort":[1924]}
Title | Nikostratos der Platoniker |
Type | Article |
Language | German |
Date | 1922 |
Journal | Hermes |
Volume | 57 |
Issue | 4 |
Pages | 481-517 |
Categories | no categories |
Author(s) | Praechter, Karl |
Editor(s) | |
Translator(s) |
Als Beitrag zur Vor- und Entwicklungsgeschichte des Neu platonismus auf einem Teilgebiet seiner Lehre möchte [...] die vorliegende Untersuchung betrachtet werden. Ich selbst habe zu zeigen versucht, daß der alexandrinische Neuplatonismus keines wegs die Linie Plotin-Porphyrios-Iamblich fortsetzt, sondern an ein früheres Stadium platonischer Lehrentwicklung anschließt. [pp. 516 f.] |
Online Resources | https://uni-koeln.sciebo.de/s/viSBRYmv6qSxA3q |
{"_index":"sire","_type":"_doc","_id":"775","_score":null,"_source":{"id":775,"authors_free":[{"id":1139,"entry_id":775,"agent_type":null,"is_normalised":null,"person_id":293,"institution_id":null,"role":{"id":1,"role_name":"author"},"free_name":"Praechter, Karl","free_first_name":"Karl","free_last_name":"Praechter","norm_person":{"id":293,"first_name":"Karl","last_name":"Praechter","full_name":"Praechter, Karl","short_ident":"","is_classical_name":null,"dnb_url":"http:\/\/d-nb.info\/gnd\/116278609","viaf_url":"","db_url":"","from_claudius":null}}],"entry_title":"Nikostratos der Platoniker","main_title":{"title":"Nikostratos der Platoniker"},"abstract":"Als Beitrag zur Vor- und Entwicklungsgeschichte des Neu\u00ad\r\nplatonismus auf einem Teilgebiet seiner Lehre m\u00f6chte [...] die \r\nvorliegende Untersuchung betrachtet werden. Ich selbst habe zu \r\nzeigen versucht, da\u00df der alexandrinische Neuplatonismus keines\u00ad\r\nwegs die Linie Plotin-Porphyrios-Iamblich fortsetzt, sondern an ein \r\nfr\u00fcheres Stadium platonischer Lehrentwicklung anschlie\u00dft. [pp. 516 f.]","btype":3,"date":"1922","language":"German","online_url":"","online_resources":"https:\/\/uni-koeln.sciebo.de\/s\/viSBRYmv6qSxA3q","doi_url":null,"categories":[],"authors":[{"id":293,"full_name":"Praechter, Karl","role":{"id":1,"role_name":"author"}}],"book":null,"booksection":null,"article":{"id":775,"journal_id":null,"journal_name":"Hermes","volume":"57","issue":"4","pages":"481-517"}},"sort":[1922]}
Title | Simplicius de anima 146. 21 |
Type | Article |
Language | English |
Date | 1922 |
Journal | Classical Philology |
Volume | 17 |
Issue | 2 |
Pages | 143-144 |
Categories | no categories |
Author(s) | Shorey, Paul |
Editor(s) | |
Translator(s) |
Note on Simplicius de anima 146. 21 |
Online Resources | https://uni-koeln.sciebo.de/s/AQundZhqjlESI3F |
{"_index":"sire","_type":"_doc","_id":"852","_score":null,"_source":{"id":852,"authors_free":[{"id":1256,"entry_id":852,"agent_type":null,"is_normalised":null,"person_id":321,"institution_id":null,"role":{"id":1,"role_name":"author"},"free_name":"Shorey, Paul","free_first_name":"Paul","free_last_name":"Shorey","norm_person":{"id":321,"first_name":"Paul","last_name":"Shorey","full_name":"Shorey, Paul","short_ident":"","is_classical_name":null,"dnb_url":"http:\/\/d-nb.info\/gnd\/101356426X","viaf_url":"","db_url":"","from_claudius":null}}],"entry_title":"Simplicius de anima 146. 21","main_title":{"title":"Simplicius de anima 146. 21"},"abstract":"Note on Simplicius de anima 146. 21","btype":3,"date":"1922","language":"English","online_url":"","online_resources":"https:\/\/uni-koeln.sciebo.de\/s\/AQundZhqjlESI3F","doi_url":null,"categories":[],"authors":[{"id":321,"full_name":"Shorey, Paul","role":{"id":1,"role_name":"author"}}],"book":null,"booksection":null,"article":{"id":852,"journal_id":null,"journal_name":"Classical Philology","volume":"17","issue":"2","pages":"143-144"}},"sort":[1922]}
Title | On Simplicius De Caelo, 476, 11 sqq |
Type | Article |
Language | English |
Date | 1905 |
Journal | The Classical Review |
Volume | 19 |
Issue | 4 |
Pages | 205 |
Categories | no categories |
Author(s) | Shorey, Paul |
Editor(s) | |
Translator(s) |
Notes on On Simplicius De Caelo, 476, 11 sqq. |
Online Resources | https://uni-koeln.sciebo.de/s/JJdmbGUh1TLKUrg |
{"_index":"sire","_type":"_doc","_id":"1019","_score":null,"_source":{"id":1019,"authors_free":[{"id":1535,"entry_id":1019,"agent_type":null,"is_normalised":null,"person_id":321,"institution_id":null,"role":{"id":1,"role_name":"author"},"free_name":"Shorey, Paul","free_first_name":"Paul","free_last_name":"Shorey","norm_person":{"id":321,"first_name":"Paul","last_name":"Shorey","full_name":"Shorey, Paul","short_ident":"","is_classical_name":null,"dnb_url":"http:\/\/d-nb.info\/gnd\/101356426X","viaf_url":"","db_url":"","from_claudius":null}}],"entry_title":"On Simplicius De Caelo, 476, 11 sqq","main_title":{"title":"On Simplicius De Caelo, 476, 11 sqq"},"abstract":"Notes on On Simplicius De Caelo, 476, 11 sqq.","btype":3,"date":"1905","language":"English","online_url":"","online_resources":"https:\/\/uni-koeln.sciebo.de\/s\/JJdmbGUh1TLKUrg","doi_url":null,"categories":[],"authors":[{"id":321,"full_name":"Shorey, Paul","role":{"id":1,"role_name":"author"}}],"book":null,"booksection":null,"article":{"id":1019,"journal_id":null,"journal_name":"The Classical Review","volume":"19","issue":"4","pages":"205"}},"sort":[1905]}
Title | Musonius and Simplicius |
Type | Article |
Language | English |
Date | 1903 |
Journal | The Classical Review |
Volume | 17 |
Issue | 1 |
Pages | 23-24 |
Categories | no categories |
Author(s) | Mayor, John E.B. |
Editor(s) | |
Translator(s) |
Notes about Musonius and Simplicius |
Online Resources | https://uni-koeln.sciebo.de/s/rOykf8wpSM6TmcD |
{"_index":"sire","_type":"_doc","_id":"988","_score":null,"_source":{"id":988,"authors_free":[{"id":1489,"entry_id":988,"agent_type":null,"is_normalised":null,"person_id":242,"institution_id":null,"role":{"id":1,"role_name":"author"},"free_name":"Mayor, John E.B.","free_first_name":"John E.B.","free_last_name":"Mayor","norm_person":{"id":242,"first_name":"John E. B.","last_name":"Mayor","full_name":"Mayor, John E. B.","short_ident":"","is_classical_name":null,"dnb_url":"http:\/\/d-nb.info\/gnd\/129593915","viaf_url":"","db_url":"","from_claudius":null}}],"entry_title":"Musonius and Simplicius","main_title":{"title":"Musonius and Simplicius"},"abstract":"Notes about Musonius and Simplicius","btype":3,"date":"1903","language":"English","online_url":"","online_resources":"https:\/\/uni-koeln.sciebo.de\/s\/rOykf8wpSM6TmcD","doi_url":null,"categories":[],"authors":[{"id":242,"full_name":"Mayor, John E. B.","role":{"id":1,"role_name":"author"}}],"book":null,"booksection":null,"article":{"id":988,"journal_id":null,"journal_name":"The Classical Review","volume":"17","issue":"1","pages":"23-24"}},"sort":[1903]}
Title | Simpl. in Aristot. de Caelo p. 370, 29 ff. H |
Type | Article |
Language | German |
Date | 1924 |
Journal | Hermes |
Volume | 59 |
Issue | 1 |
Pages | 118-119 |
Categories | no categories |
Author(s) | Praechter, Karl |
Editor(s) | |
Translator(s) |
Online Resources | https://uni-koeln.sciebo.de/s/zc8efUUHCZuTFnA |
{"_index":"sire","_type":"_doc","_id":"1477","_score":null,"_source":{"id":1477,"authors_free":[{"id":2558,"entry_id":1477,"agent_type":"person","is_normalised":1,"person_id":293,"institution_id":null,"role":{"id":1,"role_name":"author"},"free_name":"Praechter, Karl","free_first_name":"Karl","free_last_name":"Praechter","norm_person":{"id":293,"first_name":"Karl","last_name":"Praechter","full_name":"Praechter, Karl","short_ident":"","is_classical_name":null,"dnb_url":"http:\/\/d-nb.info\/gnd\/116278609","viaf_url":"","db_url":"","from_claudius":null}}],"entry_title":"Simpl. in Aristot. de Caelo p. 370, 29 ff. H","main_title":{"title":"Simpl. in Aristot. de Caelo p. 370, 29 ff. H"},"abstract":"","btype":3,"date":"1924","language":"German","online_url":"","online_resources":"https:\/\/uni-koeln.sciebo.de\/s\/zc8efUUHCZuTFnA","doi_url":null,"categories":[],"authors":[{"id":293,"full_name":"Praechter, Karl","role":{"id":1,"role_name":"author"}}],"book":null,"booksection":null,"article":{"id":1477,"journal_id":null,"journal_name":"Hermes","volume":"59","issue":"1","pages":"118-119"}},"sort":["Simpl. in Aristot. de Caelo p. 370, 29 ff. H"]}
Title | Simplicius de anima 146. 21 |
Type | Article |
Language | English |
Date | 1922 |
Journal | Classical Philology |
Volume | 17 |
Issue | 2 |
Pages | 143-144 |
Categories | no categories |
Author(s) | Shorey, Paul |
Editor(s) | |
Translator(s) |
Note on Simplicius de anima 146. 21 |
Online Resources | https://uni-koeln.sciebo.de/s/AQundZhqjlESI3F |
{"_index":"sire","_type":"_doc","_id":"852","_score":null,"_source":{"id":852,"authors_free":[{"id":1256,"entry_id":852,"agent_type":null,"is_normalised":null,"person_id":321,"institution_id":null,"role":{"id":1,"role_name":"author"},"free_name":"Shorey, Paul","free_first_name":"Paul","free_last_name":"Shorey","norm_person":{"id":321,"first_name":"Paul","last_name":"Shorey","full_name":"Shorey, Paul","short_ident":"","is_classical_name":null,"dnb_url":"http:\/\/d-nb.info\/gnd\/101356426X","viaf_url":"","db_url":"","from_claudius":null}}],"entry_title":"Simplicius de anima 146. 21","main_title":{"title":"Simplicius de anima 146. 21"},"abstract":"Note on Simplicius de anima 146. 21","btype":3,"date":"1922","language":"English","online_url":"","online_resources":"https:\/\/uni-koeln.sciebo.de\/s\/AQundZhqjlESI3F","doi_url":null,"categories":[],"authors":[{"id":321,"full_name":"Shorey, Paul","role":{"id":1,"role_name":"author"}}],"book":null,"booksection":null,"article":{"id":852,"journal_id":null,"journal_name":"Classical Philology","volume":"17","issue":"2","pages":"143-144"}},"sort":["Simplicius de anima 146. 21"]}
Title | The Homoiomeries of Anaxagoras |
Type | Article |
Language | English |
Date | 1927 |
Journal | The Classical Quarterly |
Volume | 21 |
Issue | 3/4 |
Pages | 133-141 |
Categories | no categories |
Author(s) | Leon, Philip |
Editor(s) | |
Translator(s) |
[Conclusion, p. 141]: Anaxagoras does indeed, as he has been said to do, represent the culminating point of the enquiry into the one bto-tv. That simple enquiry for a simple unity becomes curiously complex, just because of the very simplicity and the thorough-going and uncompromising nature of Anaxagoras' logical mind. It has with him reached a stage where it must become transformed and pass on the one hand into logic in Plato, into the enquiry about the nature of predication through Gorgias and Antisthenes, and on the other hand into metaphysics, the theory of ideas, also in Plato. This central position of Anaxagoras is made clear by the passage discussed, according to which, I think, in considering the 'homoiomeries,' we should look upon parts as 'homoiomerous' primarily to the whole i~c6otov, and only secondarily to subordinate wholes. Indeed, it is implied in Anaxagoras' principle that there are only two entities which are properly wholes, the 0c0/cpo and voDv^. To call anything else a whole is more or less arbitrary, a principle not unworthy of the most thorough-going of modern absolutists. |
Online Resources | https://uni-koeln.sciebo.de/s/FXHNwY19loMmfLj |
{"_index":"sire","_type":"_doc","_id":"733","_score":null,"_source":{"id":733,"authors_free":[{"id":1096,"entry_id":733,"agent_type":null,"is_normalised":null,"person_id":245,"institution_id":null,"role":{"id":1,"role_name":"author"},"free_name":"Leon, Philip","free_first_name":"Philip","free_last_name":"Leon","norm_person":{"id":245,"first_name":"Philip","last_name":"Leon","full_name":"Leon, Philip","short_ident":"","is_classical_name":null,"dnb_url":"","viaf_url":"","db_url":"","from_claudius":null}}],"entry_title":"The Homoiomeries of Anaxagoras","main_title":{"title":"The Homoiomeries of Anaxagoras"},"abstract":"[Conclusion, p. 141]: Anaxagoras does indeed, as he has been said to do, represent the \r\nculminating point of the enquiry into the one bto-tv. That simple enquiry \r\nfor a simple unity becomes curiously complex, just because of the very \r\nsimplicity and the thorough-going and uncompromising nature of Anaxagoras' \r\nlogical mind. It has with him reached a stage where it must become \r\ntransformed and pass on the one hand into logic in Plato, into the enquiry \r\nabout the nature of predication through Gorgias and Antisthenes, and on the \r\nother hand into metaphysics, the theory of ideas, also in Plato. This central \r\nposition of Anaxagoras is made clear by the passage discussed, according \r\nto which, I think, in considering the 'homoiomeries,' we should look upon \r\nparts as 'homoiomerous' primarily to the whole i~c6otov, and only secondarily \r\nto subordinate wholes. Indeed, it is implied in Anaxagoras' principle that \r\nthere are only two entities which are properly wholes, the 0c0\/cpo and voDv^. To call anything else a whole is more or less arbitrary, a principle not \r\nunworthy of the most thorough-going of modern absolutists. ","btype":3,"date":"1927","language":"English","online_url":"","online_resources":"https:\/\/uni-koeln.sciebo.de\/s\/FXHNwY19loMmfLj","doi_url":null,"categories":[],"authors":[{"id":245,"full_name":"Leon, Philip","role":{"id":1,"role_name":"author"}}],"book":null,"booksection":null,"article":{"id":733,"journal_id":null,"journal_name":"The Classical Quarterly","volume":"21","issue":"3\/4","pages":"133-141"}},"sort":["The Homoiomeries of Anaxagoras"]}
Title | The Parmenides of Plato and the Origin of the Neoplatonic 'One' |
Type | Article |
Language | English |
Date | 1928 |
Journal | Classical Quarterly |
Volume | 22 |
Issue | 3/4 (Jul. - Oct., 1928), |
Pages | 129–142 |
Categories | no categories |
Author(s) | Dodds, Eric R. |
Editor(s) | |
Translator(s) |
THE last phase of Greek philosophy has until recently been less intelli- gently studied than any other, and in our understanding of its development there are still lamentable lacunae. Three errors in particular have in the past prevented a proper appreciation of Plotinus' place in the history of philosophy. When this false trail was at length abandoned the fashion for orientalizing explanations persisted in another guise: to the earliest historians of Neo- platonism, Simon and Vacherot, the school of Plotinus was (in defiance of geographical facts) 'the school of Alexandria,' and its inspiration was mainly Egyptian. Vacherot says of Neoplatonism that it is 'essentially and radically oriental, having nothing of Greek thought but its language and procedure.' Few would be found to-day to subscribe to so sweeping a pronouncement; but the existence of an important oriental element in Plotinus' thought is still affirmed by many French and German writers. [p. 129] |
Online Resources | https://uni-koeln.sciebo.de/s/ElUfvVkaaeLIJVk |
{"_index":"sire","_type":"_doc","_id":"554","_score":null,"_source":{"id":554,"authors_free":[{"id":783,"entry_id":554,"agent_type":null,"is_normalised":null,"person_id":65,"institution_id":null,"role":{"id":1,"role_name":"author"},"free_name":"Dodds, Eric R. ","free_first_name":"Eric R. ","free_last_name":"Dodds","norm_person":{"id":65,"first_name":"Eric R. ","last_name":"Dodds","full_name":"Dodds, Eric R. ","short_ident":"","is_classical_name":null,"dnb_url":"http:\/\/d-nb.info\/gnd\/123026288","viaf_url":"","db_url":"","from_claudius":null}}],"entry_title":"The Parmenides of Plato and the Origin of the Neoplatonic 'One' ","main_title":{"title":"The Parmenides of Plato and the Origin of the Neoplatonic 'One' "},"abstract":"THE last phase of Greek philosophy has until recently been less intelli- \r\ngently studied than any other, and in our understanding of its development \r\nthere are still lamentable lacunae. Three errors in particular have in the past \r\nprevented a proper appreciation of Plotinus' place in the history of philosophy. When this false trail was at length abandoned the fashion for orientalizing \r\nexplanations persisted in another guise: to the earliest historians of Neo- \r\nplatonism, Simon and Vacherot, the school of Plotinus was (in defiance of \r\ngeographical facts) 'the school of Alexandria,' and its inspiration was mainly \r\nEgyptian. Vacherot says of Neoplatonism that it is 'essentially and radically \r\noriental, having nothing of Greek thought but its language and procedure.' \r\nFew would be found to-day to subscribe to so sweeping a pronouncement; but \r\nthe existence of an important oriental element in Plotinus' thought is still \r\naffirmed by many French and German writers. [p. 129]","btype":3,"date":"1928","language":"English","online_url":"","online_resources":"https:\/\/uni-koeln.sciebo.de\/s\/ElUfvVkaaeLIJVk","doi_url":null,"categories":[],"authors":[{"id":65,"full_name":"Dodds, Eric R. ","role":{"id":1,"role_name":"author"}}],"book":null,"booksection":null,"article":{"id":554,"journal_id":null,"journal_name":"Classical Quarterly","volume":"22","issue":"3\/4 (Jul. - Oct., 1928),","pages":"129\u2013142"}},"sort":["The Parmenides of Plato and the Origin of the Neoplatonic 'One' "]}
Title | The Unity of Empedocles' Thought |
Type | Article |
Language | English |
Date | 1949 |
Journal | The American Journal of Philology |
Volume | 70 |
Issue | 2 |
Pages | 142-158 |
Categories | no categories |
Author(s) | Long, Herbert S. |
Editor(s) | |
Translator(s) |
In this paper I shall first state the problem of the unity of Empedocles' thought, then consider two difficulties in the way of a solution and the effect that not observing them has had, and finally propose and attempt to justify what appears to me to be a reasonable explanation of the problem. [p. 142] |
Online Resources | https://uni-koeln.sciebo.de/s/Glli8IC1bpJB9RU |
{"_index":"sire","_type":"_doc","_id":"731","_score":null,"_source":{"id":731,"authors_free":[{"id":1094,"entry_id":731,"agent_type":null,"is_normalised":null,"person_id":456,"institution_id":null,"role":{"id":1,"role_name":"author"},"free_name":"Long, Herbert S.","free_first_name":"Herbert S.","free_last_name":"Long","norm_person":{"id":456,"first_name":"Herbert, S.","last_name":"Long","full_name":"Long, Herbert, S.","short_ident":"","is_classical_name":null,"dnb_url":"","viaf_url":"","db_url":"","from_claudius":null}}],"entry_title":"The Unity of Empedocles' Thought","main_title":{"title":"The Unity of Empedocles' Thought"},"abstract":"In this paper I shall first \r\nstate the problem of the unity of Empedocles' thought, then \r\nconsider two difficulties in the way of a solution and the effect \r\nthat not observing them has had, and finally propose and attempt to justify what appears to me to be a reasonable explanation of \r\nthe problem. [p. 142]","btype":3,"date":"1949","language":"English","online_url":"","online_resources":"https:\/\/uni-koeln.sciebo.de\/s\/Glli8IC1bpJB9RU","doi_url":null,"categories":[],"authors":[{"id":456,"full_name":"Long, Herbert, S.","role":{"id":1,"role_name":"author"}}],"book":null,"booksection":null,"article":{"id":731,"journal_id":null,"journal_name":"The American Journal of Philology","volume":"70","issue":"2","pages":"142-158"}},"sort":["The Unity of Empedocles' Thought"]}
Title | Un vers méconnu des Oracles Chaldaïques dans Simplicius. In de Caelo II.1, 284a14 (p. 375. 9 ss. Heib) |
Type | Article |
Language | French |
Date | 1948 |
Journal | Symbolae Osloenses |
Volume | 26 |
Pages | 75–77 |
Categories | no categories |
Author(s) | Festugière, André-Jean |
Editor(s) | |
Translator(s) |
Online Resources | https://uni-koeln.sciebo.de/s/dKy5vRHddyAHLV3 |
{"_index":"sire","_type":"_doc","_id":"549","_score":null,"_source":{"id":549,"authors_free":[{"id":773,"entry_id":549,"agent_type":null,"is_normalised":null,"person_id":112,"institution_id":null,"role":{"id":1,"role_name":"author"},"free_name":"Festugi\u00e8re, Andr\u00e9-Jean","free_first_name":"Andr\u00e9-Jean","free_last_name":"Festugi\u00e8re","norm_person":{"id":112,"first_name":"Andr\u00e9-Jean","last_name":"Festugi\u00e8re","full_name":"Festugi\u00e8re, Andr\u00e9-Jean","short_ident":"","is_classical_name":null,"dnb_url":"http:\/\/d-nb.info\/gnd\/117758256","viaf_url":"","db_url":"","from_claudius":null}}],"entry_title":"Un vers m\u00e9connu des Oracles Chalda\u00efques dans Simplicius. In de Caelo II.1, 284a14 (p. 375. 9 ss. Heib)","main_title":{"title":"Un vers m\u00e9connu des Oracles Chalda\u00efques dans Simplicius. In de Caelo II.1, 284a14 (p. 375. 9 ss. Heib)"},"abstract":"","btype":3,"date":"1948","language":"French","online_url":"","online_resources":"https:\/\/uni-koeln.sciebo.de\/s\/dKy5vRHddyAHLV3","doi_url":null,"categories":[],"authors":[{"id":112,"full_name":"Festugi\u00e8re, Andr\u00e9-Jean","role":{"id":1,"role_name":"author"}}],"book":null,"booksection":null,"article":{"id":549,"journal_id":null,"journal_name":"Symbolae Osloenses","volume":"26","issue":"","pages":"75\u201377"}},"sort":["Un vers m\u00e9connu des Oracles Chalda\u00efques dans Simplicius. In de Caelo II.1, 284a14 (p. 375. 9 ss. Heib)"]}
Title | Zeno of Elea's Attacks on Plurality |
Type | Article |
Language | English |
Date | 1942 |
Journal | The American Journal of Philology |
Volume | 63 |
Issue | 1 |
Pages | 1-25 |
Categories | no categories |
Author(s) | Fraenkel, Hermann |
Editor(s) | |
Translator(s) |
In recent decades students of mathematics, philosophy, and the classics have again and again raised their voices 1 to vindicate the serious importance of Zeno's paradoxes of motion (Vorsokr.2 29 A 25-28 - Lee,3 nos. 19-36), not even excluding the Stadium. No longer can the problem implied in the paradoxes be disposed of by simply pointing out that time and space are equally divisible. The question which is at the bottom of all four of them is far more profound. [...] Fur- thermore, it has been shown that Aristotle, when qriticizing the paradoxes, was not concerned conscientiously to adjust his objec- tions to that which the historical Zeno had tried to prove, or rather disprove. [...] If it is thus established that Zeno's syllogisms must not necessarily be condemned as a futile play of dialectics 6 and that Aristotle's censure fails to do Zeno justice, a road seems to be open to a full rehabilitation and, perhaps, glorification. But one doubt remains. How adequately did the real Zeno actually deal with the problems he had in hand? And how sincere was he about them? [pp. 1 f.] |
Online Resources | https://uni-koeln.sciebo.de/s/thc7ngkOcyyG7Iz |
{"_index":"sire","_type":"_doc","_id":"746","_score":null,"_source":{"id":746,"authors_free":[{"id":1109,"entry_id":746,"agent_type":null,"is_normalised":null,"person_id":115,"institution_id":null,"role":{"id":1,"role_name":"author"},"free_name":"Fraenkel, Hermann","free_first_name":"Hermann","free_last_name":"Fraenkel","norm_person":{"id":115,"first_name":"Hermann","last_name":"Fraenkel","full_name":"Fraenkel, Hermann","short_ident":"","is_classical_name":null,"dnb_url":"http:\/\/d-nb.info\/gnd\/119051478","viaf_url":"","db_url":"","from_claudius":null}}],"entry_title":"Zeno of Elea's Attacks on Plurality","main_title":{"title":"Zeno of Elea's Attacks on Plurality"},"abstract":"In recent decades students of mathematics, philosophy, and \r\nthe classics have again and again raised their voices 1 to vindicate \r\nthe serious importance of Zeno's paradoxes of motion (Vorsokr.2 29 A 25-28 - Lee,3 nos. 19-36), not even excluding the Stadium. \r\nNo longer can the problem implied in the paradoxes be disposed of by simply pointing out that time and space are equally divisible. The question which is at the bottom of all four of \r\nthem is far more profound. [...] Fur- \r\nthermore, it has been shown that Aristotle, when qriticizing the \r\nparadoxes, was not concerned conscientiously to adjust his objec- tions to that which the historical Zeno had tried to prove, or \r\nrather disprove. [...] If it is \r\nthus established that Zeno's syllogisms must not necessarily be \r\ncondemned as a futile play of dialectics 6 and that Aristotle's \r\ncensure fails to do Zeno justice, a road seems to be open to a \r\nfull rehabilitation and, perhaps, glorification. But one doubt \r\nremains. How adequately did the real Zeno actually deal with \r\nthe problems he had in hand? And how sincere was he about \r\nthem? [pp. 1 f.]","btype":3,"date":"1942","language":"English","online_url":"","online_resources":"https:\/\/uni-koeln.sciebo.de\/s\/thc7ngkOcyyG7Iz","doi_url":null,"categories":[],"authors":[{"id":115,"full_name":"Fraenkel, Hermann","role":{"id":1,"role_name":"author"}}],"book":null,"booksection":null,"article":{"id":746,"journal_id":null,"journal_name":"The American Journal of Philology","volume":"63","issue":"1","pages":"1-25"}},"sort":["Zeno of Elea's Attacks on Plurality"]}
Title | Zur Entstehung und zum Wesen des griechischen wissenschaftlichen Kommentars |
Type | Article |
Language | German |
Date | 1932 |
Journal | Hermes |
Volume | 67 |
Issue | 4 |
Pages | 397-412 |
Categories | no categories |
Author(s) | Geffcken, Johannes |
Editor(s) | |
Translator(s) |
In dem Text wird die Entstehung und das Wesen des antiken Kommentars untersucht. Es wird aufgezeigt, dass der Kommentar in der Antike als eine Art praktische Notwendigkeit angesehen wurde, sei es in Form von Erklärungen zu sakralen Gesetzen, Schulunterricht oder Homerparaphrasen. Die Aristotelische Schule beeinflusste den Geist aller wissenschaftlichen Kommentare. Der Autor schlägt vor, dass eine wirkliche Geschichte des antiken Kommentars notwendig ist, um die Kontinuität und die individuellen Beiträge der Forscher und Denker zu verstehen. [introduction/conclusion] |
Online Resources | https://uni-koeln.sciebo.de/s/lev9vfokt9KpzHD |
{"_index":"sire","_type":"_doc","_id":"1314","_score":null,"_source":{"id":1314,"authors_free":[{"id":1948,"entry_id":1314,"agent_type":"person","is_normalised":1,"person_id":126,"institution_id":null,"role":{"id":1,"role_name":"author"},"free_name":"Geffcken, Johannes","free_first_name":"Johannes","free_last_name":"Geffcken","norm_person":{"id":126,"first_name":"Johannes","last_name":"Geffcken","full_name":"Geffcken, Johannes","short_ident":"","is_classical_name":null,"dnb_url":"http:\/\/d-nb.info\/gnd\/120376644","viaf_url":"","db_url":"","from_claudius":null}}],"entry_title":"Zur Entstehung und zum Wesen des griechischen wissenschaftlichen Kommentars","main_title":{"title":"Zur Entstehung und zum Wesen des griechischen wissenschaftlichen Kommentars"},"abstract":"In dem Text wird die Entstehung und das Wesen des antiken Kommentars untersucht. Es wird aufgezeigt, dass der Kommentar in der Antike als eine Art praktische Notwendigkeit angesehen wurde, sei es in Form von Erkl\u00e4rungen zu sakralen Gesetzen, Schulunterricht oder Homerparaphrasen. Die Aristotelische Schule beeinflusste den Geist aller wissenschaftlichen Kommentare. Der Autor schl\u00e4gt vor, dass eine wirkliche Geschichte des antiken Kommentars notwendig ist, um die Kontinuit\u00e4t und die individuellen Beitr\u00e4ge der Forscher und Denker zu verstehen. [introduction\/conclusion]","btype":3,"date":"1932","language":"German","online_url":"","online_resources":"https:\/\/uni-koeln.sciebo.de\/s\/lev9vfokt9KpzHD","doi_url":null,"categories":[],"authors":[{"id":126,"full_name":"Geffcken, Johannes","role":{"id":1,"role_name":"author"}}],"book":null,"booksection":null,"article":{"id":1314,"journal_id":null,"journal_name":"Hermes","volume":"67","issue":"4","pages":"397-412"}},"sort":["Zur Entstehung und zum Wesen des griechischen wissenschaftlichen Kommentars"]}